79C3C34C52B45572883A05D425EB0F82
WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public Health Surveillance
https://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/handle/10665/255721/9789241512657-eng.pdf?sequence=1
http://leaux.net/URLS/ConvertAPI Text Files/E6F36C87591BE386319D514777213AAD.en.txt
Examining the file media/Synopses/E6F36C87591BE386319D514777213AAD.html:
This file was generated: 2020-12-01 09:28:27
Indicators in focus are typically shown highlighted in yellow; |
Peer Indicators (that share the same Vulnerability association) are shown highlighted in pink; |
"Outside" Indicators (those that do NOT share the same Vulnerability association) are shown highlighted in green; |
Trigger Words/Phrases are shown highlighted in gray. |
Link to Orphaned Trigger Words (Appendix (Indicator List, Indicator Peers, Trigger Words, Type/Vulnerability/Indicator Overlay)
Applicable Type / Vulnerability / Indicator Overlay for this Input
Political / Refugee Status
Searching for indicator refugee:
(return to top)
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: The HIV oral test on a brothel bed in Belém do Pará, Brazil.
p.000035: Source: Laura Murray
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guideline 10. Governments and others who hold surveillance data must ensure that identifiable data are appropriately
p.000036: secured.
p.000036:
...
Political / criminal
Searching for indicator criminal:
(return to top)
p.000021: outbreaks, framed as they were by concern for groups in conditions of tremendous vulner- ability and the ways
p.000021: in which outbreaks can become crises, further amplified by fear and distrust, places greater emphasis on
p.000021: human rights. Given the need to make decisions in
p.000021:
p.000022: 22
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: the face of uncertainty, they also stress utility, proportionality and efficacy.
p.000022:
p.000022: The ethical considerations outlined above and repeated and amplified in the guidelines that follow are, in the
p.000022: estimation of this commit- tee, central to justification of surveillance as a core activity, beyond outbreaks
p.000022: or infectious disease situations. They must be applied in situations that may vary in fundamental ways. The
p.000022: guidelines recognize that trade-offs of values are sometimes inevitable. The local tra- ditions and
p.000022: priorities in countries may some- times result in a different balance between competing values and
p.000022: priorities. It is important to stress, however, that not all trade-offs are morally acceptable. Local, national,
p.000022: or regional circumstances may be characterized by gross injustice or violations of human rights. In these
p.000022: contexts, rather than serving the common good, public health surveillance may be used as an
p.000022: instrument for violation of respect for persons, equity, and justice. In countries where sex work is a
p.000022: criminal offense, for example, HIV surveillance can be used for oppression.
p.000022: Likewise, an occupational disease surveil- lance system that results in routine dismissal of workers
p.000022: affected by silicosis, black lung, or asbestosis would be unacceptable. Appeal to “trade-offs” under such
p.000022: circumstances could well be a pretext for further oppression and should be guarded against.
p.000022:
p.000022: The State is a source of both intrusion and protection. Some disease burdens and forms of health
p.000022: oppression simply cannot be made visible without State-sponsored surveillance (50). On the one hand,
p.000022: surveillance makes public health interventions to address inequi- ties possible. On the other hand,
p.000022: surveillance may be used to impose additional burdens on those who are already disadvantaged. The only assurance
p.000022: that surveillance will amount to neither privilege nor punishment is atten- tion to the ethical
p.000022: considerations described above: both burdens and benefits should be critically weighed and then fairly
p.000022: distributed in a transparent manner in which States are held accountable.
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000023: 23
p.000023:
p.000023: IV. Guidelines
p.000023: As a consequence of the development of ethi- cal norms for the conduct of research during the past few
...
Political / migrant
Searching for indicator migrant:
(return to top)
p.000033: and to put in place processes to mitigate harm. Without continuous monitoring, mitigation is impos- sible.
p.000033: This is vital, not only because it is wrong to cause unnecessary harm, but also because harm – to both
p.000033: individuals and communi- ties, such as loss of property value or tourism dollars – may also damage public
p.000033: trust in the programme and in public health in general. (See guidelines 5, 12 and 13 and the discus-
p.000033: sion of good governance in section III.)
p.000033:
p.000033: In some instances, countries have provided compensation for the harm that might
p.000033:
p.000033: inevitably accompany surveillance. In the con- text of SARS, Chinese Taipei gave people who were quarantined the
p.000033: equivalent of US$ 147 (68). Basic welfare benefits or sick pay for those deprived of work as a result
p.000033: of surveil- lance are other possibilities. The possibility of compensation should not, however, pose a
p.000033: barrier to surveillance (69).
p.000033:
p.000033: There are many different types of harm: eco- nomic, legal, psychological, social (and reputa- tional) and
p.000033: physical. All should be considered in relation to surveillance (70-72). For example, a migrant or a person in another
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
...
Political / person under arrest
Searching for indicator arrest:
(return to top)
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
p.000034: however, mitigation strategies can ensure that risks for harm are dealt with adequately. Once harm or
...
Political / political affiliation
Searching for indicator party:
(return to top)
p.000005: Attribution-NonCommercial- ShareAlike 3.0 IGO licence (CC BY-NC-SA 3.0 IGO;
p.000005: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/igo).
p.000005:
p.000005: Under the terms of this licence, you may copy, redistribute and adapt the work for non-commercial purposes, pro- vided
p.000005: the work is appropriately cited, as indicated below. In any use of this work, there should be no suggestion that WHO
p.000005: endorses any specific organization, products or services. The use of the WHO logo is not permitted. If you adapt the
p.000005: work, then you must license your work under the same or equivalent Creative Commons licence. If you create a
p.000005: translation of this work, you should add the following disclaimer along with the suggested cita- tion: “This
p.000005: translation was not created by the World Health Organization (WHO). WHO is not responsible for the content or accuracy
p.000005: of this translation. The original English edition shall be the binding and authentic edition”.
p.000005:
p.000005: Any mediation relating to disputes arising under the licence shall be conducted in accordance with the media- tion
p.000005: rules of the World Intellectual Property Organization.
p.000005:
p.000005: Suggested citation. WHO guidelines on ethical issues in public health surveillance. Geneva: World Health
p.000005: Organization; 2017. Licence: CC BY-NC-SA 3.0 IGO.
p.000005:
p.000005: Cataloguing-in-Publication (CIP) data. CIP data are available at http://apps.who.int/iris.
p.000005:
p.000005: Sales, rights and licensing. To purchase WHO publications, see http://apps.who.int/bookorders. To submit
p.000005: requests for commercial use and queries on rights and licensing, see http://www.who.int/about/licensing.
p.000005:
p.000005: Third-party materials. If you wish to reuse material from this work that is attributed to a third party, such as
p.000005: tables, figures or images, it is your responsibility to determine whether permission is needed for that reuse and to
p.000005: obtain permission from the copyright holder. The risk of claims resulting from infringement of any
p.000005: third- party-owned component in the work rests solely with the user.
p.000005:
p.000005: General disclaimers. The designations employed and the presentation of the material in this publication do not imply
p.000005: the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of WHO concerning the legal status of any country, territory, city
p.000005: or area or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. Dotted and dashed lines
p.000005: on maps represent approximate border lines for which there may not yet be full agreement.
p.000005:
p.000005: The mention of specific companies or of certain manufacturers’ products does not imply that they are endorsed or
p.000005: recommended by WHO in preference to others of a similar nature that are not mentioned. Errors and omis- sions excepted,
p.000005: the names of proprietary products are distinguished by initial capital letters.
p.000005:
p.000005: All reasonable precautions have been taken by WHO to verify the information contained in this publication. However, the
p.000005: published material is being distributed without warranty of any kind, either expressed or implied. The responsibility
p.000005: for the interpretation and use of the material lies with the reader. In no event shall WHO be liable for damages
p.000005: arising from its use.
p.000005:
p.000005: Table of Contents
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: Foreword
p.000005: 5
p.000005: Acknowledgements
p.000007: 7
p.000007: I. Introduction
p.000010: 10
p.000010: II. Background
p.000014: 14
p.000014: Defining public health surveillance
p.000014: 14
p.000014: Surveillance: ethics, law and history
p.000016: 16
p.000016: III. Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000019: 19
p.000019: Existing guidelines
p.000019: 19
...
Searching for indicator political:
(return to top)
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
p.000010: when a public health crisis becomes a “threat to international peace and security” does surveillance become a
p.000010: priority for wealthy countries (3). But even when sur- veillance is a priority, fragmented, unlinked or
p.000010: consolidated data sets remain a problem for their effective use for public health purposes.
p.000010:
p.000010: While surveillance is often conducted without public knowledge or concern when the risk for stigma,
...
p.000011: disease. Given the zoonotic ori- gin of many of the conditions, surveillance will increasingly involve monitoring
p.000011: the animal– human interface. For example, surveillance of food and animal feed for pathogens must be
p.000011: linked to surveillance for the same pathogens in humans.
p.000011:
p.000011: Surveillance is conducted in a context in which there have been significant advances in the capacity to collect
p.000011: and share data from previ- ously unimagined sources, such as social media or geospatial mobile phone data.
p.000011: There have been parallel technological leaps in possibili- ties for identifying disease; genetic analysis, as
p.000011: just one example, allows rapid identification of pathogens or pathogenic strains. At the same time, inequalities within
p.000011: societies and within the global community have become more marked. There are growing gulfs in the capacity of dif-
p.000011: ferent nations and locales to take advantage of technological change. Civil conflicts in dif- ferent
p.000011: countries inevitably trigger health crises
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011: Dog and pig vendor at market day, Atsabe, Ermera.
p.000011: Source: WHO / SEARO /Joao Soares Gusmao
p.000011:
p.000011: that draw the attention of both United Nations agencies and humanitarian organizations. Cri- sis situations, in
p.000011: turn, deepen inequalities and create additional barriers to surveillance and intervention in conflict zones (3).
p.000011:
p.000011: This remarkable epidemiological, social, eco- nomic, political and technological global landscape
p.000011: makes it imperative to fill the gap in international guidelines and to address the ethics of public
p.000011: health surveillance explicitly. That is the aim of these international guide- lines on the ethics of public
p.000011: health surveillance. They were prepared by an international group of experts in surveillance, epidemiological
p.000011: research, bioethics, public health ethics and human rights. The authors of these guidelines represent leading
p.000011: research institutions and also nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) either involved in surveillance or
p.000011: representing groups and populations with a vital interest in both the benefits and burdens of surveillance. The authors
p.000011: also represent countries in both the south and north, with different political systems, social values and
p.000011: priorities.
p.000011:
p.000011: The guidelines were prepared in collaboration with the global network of WHO Collaborating
p.000011:
p.000012: 12
p.000012: Introduction
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012: Centres for Bioethics, which initiated the proj- ect. They also drew on the technical support of the US
p.000012: Centers for Disease Control and Prevention to ensure that the guidelines took account of the actual
p.000012: procedures for and cost of data collection, analysis and dissemina- tion and can thus reasonably be
p.000012: used. The guidelines are based on a systematic literature review of relevant research and grey literature in
p.000012: accordance with the WHO Handbook for Guideline Development (5).
p.000012:
p.000012: The goal of the guideline development project was to identify key ethical considerations to guide resolution of
p.000012: controversies that may arise in surveillance, which itself is an ethical obli- gation of governments. Specific
p.000012: ethical issues are addressed in contexts that differ in terms of culture, values, resources, political
p.000012: traditions and institutional structures, with sometimes very different expectations for the impor-
p.000012: tance of individual rights, community solidar- ity and/or the good of society. The guidelines also address
p.000012: challenges that arise in contexts characterized by persistent injustice and/ or repeated violation
p.000012: of human rights. These guidelines cannot therefore provide concrete answers to all the difficult questions raised
p.000012: by
p.000012: public health surveillance. Rather, on the basis of a set of core considerations for the ethics of public health, the
p.000012: guidelines establish the duty to conduct surveillance, share data and engage communities transparently, while
p.000012: recognizing the limits of that mandate. The 17 guidelines should not be read in isolation from each other or
p.000012: from the discussion of each of them. They jointly lay out the issues that those involved in surveillance
p.000012: (including officials in government agencies, health workers involved in surveil- lance, NGOs and the private
p.000012: sector) should consider and weigh carefully when making decisions about the collection, analysis,
p.000012: shar- ing, communication and use of surveillance data.
p.000012:
p.000012: While the guidelines do not specify a mechanism for oversight, the conclusion is that, in view of the overarching
p.000012: imperative to conduct surveil- lance, analyse the data and act on the results, responsibility and
p.000012: accountability must ultimately be based on a sustainable, practical mechanism for ensuring that the ethical
p.000012: challenges posed by public health surveillance are anticipated and addressed systematically and
...
p.000015: increasingly interconnected world. They came into force in 1971 (19). The IHR impose a legal obligation on all
p.000015: Member States to have cer- tain core public health capacities, including surveillance and data collection,
p.000015: with the goal
p.000015:
p.000016: 16
p.000016: Background
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016: of preventing, controlling or responding to the international spread of disease.
p.000016:
p.000016: Experience with the SARS crisis of 2003 led the World Health Assembly to adopt a significant revision of the IHR
p.000016: on 23 May 2005 (9). While the IHR had originally focused on a short, fixed list of communicable diseases, the revised
p.000016: reg- ulations – IHR (2005) – allow flexibility to target any disease that may constitute a public health emergency of
p.000016: international concern. They also establish an obligation to create core capacity for surveillance and outbreak response
p.000016: to dis- ease and “public health events”. As of Novem- ber 2014, however, 48 countries had failed to communicate
p.000016: their capacity or plans, and another 81 had asked for extensions to com- ing into compliance (20). The
p.000016: recent outbreak of Ebola virus disease revealed that many countries had not satisfied their obligations
p.000016: under the IHR; only 64 countries – one third of those bound by the IHR – “had achieved these core
p.000016: capacities”. Nevertheless, while all countries are required to comply with the IHR, limited resources and
p.000016: political instability can pose obstacles to surveillance, and it may not be possible to overcome these obstacles
p.000016: with- out international assistance.
p.000016:
p.000016: The IHR (2005) are limited in the sense that they provide mainly a framework for gover- nance in
p.000016: addressing “public health emergen- cies of international concern”. The framework is neither for constructing
p.000016: comprehensive surveillance systems nor for grappling with the ethical issues posed by surveillance sys-
p.000016: tems and practices. International regulation, like national law and regulation, is an impor- tant tool
p.000016: that establishes a duty to conduct surveillance while also setting limits on that practice. What is legal,
p.000016: however, is not always ethical. Ethics is an essential tool for critically evaluating law, regulation and
p.000016: practice and for addressing the value conflicts that may be posed by surveillance.
p.000016: Local and national surveillance systems emerged in the nineteenth century, and almost all comprised
p.000016: physicians’ case reports. The data were initially used almost exclusively to document either social
p.000016: progress or misery (21). At the heart of the most bitter battles over individual rights and population
p.000016: health, how- ever, were surveillance measures that made intervention at the level of individuals possible, with
p.000016: the discovery of germs and the realization that many diseases were spread from person to person. Interventions
p.000016: based on communica- ble disease reports were sometimes welcomed (leading to referral to clinics, provision of food and
...
p.000020: and identifying the basis of unfair differences in health.
p.000020:
p.000020: Respect for persons: Public health eth- ics is concerned with the rights, liberty, and other interests of individuals
p.000020: as well as overall population well-being. When- ever possible, individuals should be involved in decisions
p.000020: that affect them. In some cases, individuals should be free to make their own choices; in other cases,
p.000020: when population-level interven- tions may be necessary, individuals can be consulted and involved in
p.000020: decision- making. But many individuals (such as young children) cannot make their own choices, and the State has
p.000020: an obligation to protect them and promote their long- term health interests. Undertaking pub- lic health surveillance
p.000020: is, itself, arguably an expression of respect for persons. This further requires ensuring that data about
p.000020: individuals and groups are pro- tected and risks for harm are minimized
p.000020:
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000021: 21
p.000021:
p.000021:
p.000021: to the greatest possible extent. Finally, surveillance further engenders respect for persons by making
p.000021: protection or amelioration possible.
p.000021:
p.000021: Good governance: Although good gov- ernance is not an ethical principle but rather a political aspiration, it
p.000021: is subject to a number of ethical considerations. To ensure that the ethical challenges posed by public health
p.000021: action are addressed systematically and fairly, governance mechanisms must be accountable and open to
p.000021: public scrutiny. Although pro- tection of the common good must draw on the best available evidence,
p.000021: decisions will have to be made in the face of uncertainty. Accountability, transparency and community
p.000021: engage- ment are means of justifying public policy structures that promote respect for persons,
p.000021: equity, and the common good. Transparency requires that poli- cies and procedures for surveillance be
p.000021: communicated clearly and that affected individuals or communities be aware of any decisions concerning them. Trans-
p.000021: parency also requires public reporting of the results of surveillance (in ano- nymized or aggregated form).
p.000021: Without such knowledge, communities cannot be empowered to demand government action or to protect themselves in
p.000021: the absence of alternatives.
p.000021:
p.000021: These are not the only relevant ethical consid- erations with regard to the nature of surveil- lance programmes
p.000021: and practice but the ones considered central to making decisions in the specific context of public health
p.000021: surveillance by those involved in development of these guidelines.
p.000021:
p.000021: While over the past few decades the global discourse on research ethics has come to
p.000021:
...
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000023: 23
p.000023:
p.000023: IV. Guidelines
p.000023: As a consequence of the development of ethi- cal norms for the conduct of research during the past few
p.000023: decades, research ethics com- mittees have been established in almost all countries. As surveillance does
p.000023: not fall under the rubric of research, however, there has been no systematic framework for continuous
p.000023: ethical oversight or analysis of the challenges posed by surveillance activities. The following guidelines
p.000023: are premised on the conclusion that ethical scrutiny of public health surveillance is necessary.
p.000023:
p.000023: The guidelines are, necessarily, not prescrip- tive; rather, they seek to highlight trade-offs that must be
p.000023: carefully and routinely weighed. They do not provide concrete definitions, measures, precise
p.000023: surveillance parameters or oversight mechanisms that might, on the surface, appear to make decision-making
p.000023: less complex. Concepts like “legitimate public health purpose”, “disproportionate burden”,
p.000023:
p.000023: “community engagement” and “good gov- ernance” cannot be regarded as universal yardsticks for use by
p.000023: decision-makers. Rather, agreement on definitions for use in different contexts lies at the very heart of
p.000023: the vexing political and ethical judgements that must be made: grappling with the meaning of con- cepts
p.000023: in specific local and national settings represents a first step in ethical engagement.
p.000023:
p.000023: The following guidelines, then, cover (i) the broad responsibility to undertake surveillance and subject it
p.000023: to ethical scrutiny; (ii) the obli- gation to ensure appropriate protection and rights; and (iii)
p.000023: considerations in making deci- sions about how to communicate and share surveillance data. These guidelines
p.000023: represent a starting point for the searching, sustained discussions that public health surveillance
p.000023: demands. Like other international guidelines on research ethics, the ethics of surveillance will require
p.000023: continuous review and revision in the light of experience.
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023: Kim Pai factory, Bangkok, June 2015.
p.000023: Source: WHO /Diego Rodriguez
p.000023:
p.000024: 24
p.000024: Guidelines
p.000024:
p.000024:
p.000024:
p.000024: Guideline 1. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, feasible, sustainable public health surveillance
p.000024: systems.
p.000024: Surveillance systems should have a clear purpose and a plan for data collection, analysis, use and dissemination based
p.000024: on relevant public health priorities.
p.000024:
p.000024: Member States have an ethical duty to pro- tect population health – not only that of their citizens but that
...
p.000026: context of research ethics. However, public health surveillance is currently not subject to routine
p.000026: oversight. It is the obligation of coun- tries to decide the most appropriate processes for identifying and
p.000026: addressing the ethical issues that arise in public health surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Box 1 provides some examples of existing mechanisms. Any mechanism or process should ensure
p.000026: ethical implementation of sur- veillance without itself becoming an obstacle to achieving the larger public
p.000026: health goal. (We address the nexus of surveillance and research in Guideline 16.)
p.000026: Such mechanisms of ethical oversight should effectively identify the risks and ben- efits of
p.000026: surveillance and suggest measures to enhance the benefits, minimize the risks and ensure appropriate
p.000026: weighing of the com- mon good, equity, and respect for persons. Oversight should be continuous, and any
p.000026: substantial changes proposed to the surveil- lance system should be evaluated through an “ethical lens”.
p.000026:
p.000026: Ethical monitoring of surveillance can be facili- tated and enhanced by training public health personnel. Such
p.000026: training can emphasize the importance of integrating ethical analysis early and explicitly when developing
p.000026: and imple- menting a surveillance system.
p.000026:
p.000026: While the establishment of an indepen- dent, impartial ethics oversight mechanism is warranted,
p.000026: concrete implementation will depend on the social, political, legal, and cultural context in which surveillance
p.000026: is con- ducted (52). Research usually entails discrete projects with time-limited horizons, whereas surveillance
p.000026: usually involves continuous monitoring as opposed to a one-time review. The most appropriate mechanism for
p.000026: ethical scrutiny should be chosen in a transparent, accountable fashion. (See guidelines 2 and 5 and the
p.000026: discussion of good governance in section III.)
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000027: 27
p.000027:
p.000027:
p.000027:
p.000027: Box 1. Examples of oversight mechanisms
p.000027:
p.000027: Public Health Ontario (Canada)
p.000027:
p.000027: In 2012, Public Health Ontario published “A framework for the conduct of public health initiatives”. It
p.000027: applies an integrated approach for ethics review, in which all evidence-generating initiatives undergo ethi- cal
p.000027: scrutiny proportionate to the level of risk. Its Ethics Review Board plays a vital role in helping to ensure that
p.000027: research and other initiatives conducted by Public Health Ontario are carried out in a manner that is
p.000027: consistent with the second edition of the Federal “Tri-council policy statement on ethical conduct for
p.000027: research involving humans and other relevant regulations, policies and guidelines”. The Ethics Review Board addresses
p.000027: research, evaluation, surveillance, and quality improvement projects that involve human partici- pants, their data, or
...
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054: References
p.000055: 55
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055: • What is the ethical obligation to undertake public health surveillance?
p.000055: • What are the risks of conducting disease surveillance? How should such risks be balanced against population level
p.000055: benefits?
p.000055: • When and how must relevant communities be engaged in the development of surveillance plans?
p.000055: • How should the confidentiality of surveillance data be protected?
p.000055: • What are the ethical obligations to share relevant public health surveillance data across public health
p.000055: authorities? With public health researchers? With communities and individuals who have contributed to surveillance
p.000055: systems?
p.000055: • Are there circumstances when data sharing must be strictly prohibited?
p.000055: • What institutional mechanisms should be established to ensure ethical issues are systematically addressed prior to
p.000055: data collection, use, and dissemination?
p.000055:
p.000055: These are core questions that those involved in public health surveillance have grappled with for more than a century.
p.000055: To address these and
p.000055: other pressing concerns an international group of experts has developed the WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public
p.000055: Health Surveillance. Based on a set of core ethical and policy considerations, these 17 guidelines establish the
p.000055: affirmative duties to undertake surveillance, share data, and engage communities, while recognizing the limits of
p.000055: surveillance. They will be applied in situations characterized by fundamental cultural, economic, and political
p.000055: variability. The goal, therefore, is to enable critical discussion about legitimate ethical tensions and trade-offs and
p.000055: the appropriate governance and oversight of surveillance.
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055:
p.000055: For more information, contact:
p.000055:
p.000055: Global Health Ethics
p.000055: Department of Information, Evidence and Research WHO, Geneva
p.000055:
p.000055: Email: ct_ethics@who.int
...
Political / stateless persons
Searching for indicator nation:
(return to top)
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008: The WHO Strategic Health Operations Centre (SHOC) May 3, 2009.
p.000008: Source: WHO /Christopher Black
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000009: 9
p.000009:
p.000009: I. Introduction
p.000009: Disease surveillance has been a basic public health activity since the late nineteenth century (see Table 1). It
p.000009: is the foundation for initiatives to promote human well-being at the popula- tion level. Public health
p.000009: surveillance is the bed- rock of outbreak and epidemic response, but it reaches far beyond infectious diseases.
p.000009: It can contribute to reducing inequalities: pockets of suffering that are unfair, unjust, and prevent- able
p.000009: cannot be addressed if they are not first made visible (1). It is central to understanding the increasing global
p.000009: burden of noncommuni- cable conditions. By helping to determine pat- terns and causes of morbidity and mortality,
p.000009: public health surveillance can help guarantee
p.000009:
p.000009: access to safe food, clean water, pure air, and healthy environments. Continuous envi- ronmental
p.000009: surveillance may not only identify concerns but also trigger alerts. Occupational disease surveillance can
p.000009: identify workplace exposures and lead to regulation. Surveillance can help create accountable institutions
p.000009: by providing information about health and its determinants. It can provide an evidentiary basis
p.000009: for establishing and evaluating public health policy. Surveillance, for example, will be central to the
p.000009: achievement of the United Nation’s Sustainable Development Goals. The availability of the results of
p.000009: surveillance enables and promotes policy choice. Thus, access to surveillance information can serve as
p.000009: a tool for advocacy when the results are
p.000009:
p.000009: Table 1. Dimensions of public health surveillance
p.000009: Scope
p.000009:
p.000009: Communicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Early detecting and warning of epidemics
p.000009: Noncommunicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Trend and spatial analyses
p.000009: Environmental factors
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Risk detection
p.000009: Risk factors and risk markers
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Objectives
p.000009: Generating hypotheses
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Health system
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Monitoring of health system performance
p.000009: Demographic variables
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Evaluation of control measures
p.000009: Health-related events (e.g. food and drug safety, vaccine reactions)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Registries Case reports Repeated
p.000009: surveys
p.000009: Data collection tools
p.000009: Bio-banks Secondary data sources
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Types of analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
...
p.000015: paper; in oth- ers, they are collected, stored and shared via sophisticated electronic systems. The era of
p.000015: “big data,” as discussed in section V, may hold enormous potential for the future of public health surveillance,
p.000015: broadly understood, and has already raised vexing ethical questions.
p.000015:
p.000015: In some jurisdictions, surveillance systems could soon be linked directly to electronic health
p.000015: records. Interoperability between pub- lic health surveillance data sources and clini- cal practice is within
p.000015: reach, in both the public and the private health care sectors (15). Public health data can be used to inform
p.000015: automatic decision-support systems or computational tools to trigger alerts and warnings. Research has shown,
p.000015: further, that geospatial mobile phone data could accurately describe and pre- dict the movement of individuals
p.000015: and thereby the spread of diseases like malaria and H1N1 influenza (16-18).
p.000015:
p.000015: These guidelines define public health surveil- lance systems broadly, building on the general WHO definition of
p.000015: continuous, systematic col- lection, analysis, interpretation, and sharing of health–related data for advocacy and for
p.000015: plan- ning, implementing, and evaluating public health practices. Even if systems are operative, however, new,
p.000015: focused studies are required to respond to epidemiological threats. Further, public health surveillance systems not
p.000015: only rely on but may also inform and improve clinical practice.
p.000015:
p.000015: Surveillance: ethics, law and history
p.000015:
p.000015: Nation states have established surveillance sys- tems that differ in scope and purpose. Interna- tional law and
p.000015: regulation have been important means of ensuring at least a basic level of public health surveillance in
p.000015: all countries. In 1969, the WHO Member States adopted the IHR, a revision and consolidation of the
p.000015: Inter- national Sanitary Regulations, as the frame- work for strengthening health security in an
p.000015: increasingly interconnected world. They came into force in 1971 (19). The IHR impose a legal obligation on all
p.000015: Member States to have cer- tain core public health capacities, including surveillance and data collection,
p.000015: with the goal
p.000015:
p.000016: 16
p.000016: Background
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016: of preventing, controlling or responding to the international spread of disease.
p.000016:
p.000016: Experience with the SARS crisis of 2003 led the World Health Assembly to adopt a significant revision of the IHR
p.000016: on 23 May 2005 (9). While the IHR had originally focused on a short, fixed list of communicable diseases, the revised
p.000016: reg- ulations – IHR (2005) – allow flexibility to target any disease that may constitute a public health emergency of
p.000016: international concern. They also establish an obligation to create core capacity for surveillance and outbreak response
p.000016: to dis- ease and “public health events”. As of Novem- ber 2014, however, 48 countries had failed to communicate
p.000016: their capacity or plans, and another 81 had asked for extensions to com- ing into compliance (20). The
...
p.000032: account of community values and concerns requires, at a minimum, that legiti- mate authorities undertake
p.000032: public health sur- veillance in a transparent manner in accordance with the principles of good governance. Active
p.000032: engagement of the community may involve meetings with community leaders, focus group discussions and other
p.000032: forums that provide an opportunity for members to clearly express their values and concerns (see Guideline 5
p.000032: and the discussion of good governance in section III).
p.000032:
p.000032: Box 2. Community engagement
p.000032:
p.000032: A particularly compelling, flexible method for engaging communities is democratic deliberation. This is a
p.000032: structured method for decision-making that brings together diverse stakeholders to construct solutions to complex
p.000032: policy questions. Participants engage in discussion and dialogue, communicate their perspectives respectfully, and
p.000032: provide justification for their views in a way that everyone involved can grasp. The goal is to make pressing decisions
p.000032: while considering empirical evidence, communities’ lived experience, and values. The US Bioethics Commission (64) has
p.000032: used the deliberative method as it has grappled with difficult issues fraught with tension and has made available a
p.000032: variety of training tools (65). While it is only one means of ensuring citizen involvement and is not appropriate for
p.000032: all situations, it has been a staple not only of local and national but also global decision-making. For example, in
p.000032: June 2016, (66) some 10 000 citizens in 76 countries expressed concern about climate change and recommended legally
p.000032: binding measures, including “reporting of [each nation’s] adaptation and mitigation efforts” to keep global warming
p.000032: below 2 °C. (67)
p.000032:
p.000032: Guidelines
p.000033: 33
p.000033:
p.000033:
p.000033: Guideline 8. Those responsible for surveillance should identify, evaluate, minimize and disclose risks for harm before
p.000033: surveillance is conducted. Monitoring for harm should be continuous, and, when any is identified, appropriate action
p.000033: should be taken to mitigate it.
p.000033:
p.000033: Even when public health surveillance is clearly justified to promote the common good, Mem- ber States and those
p.000033: responsible for conduct- ing surveillance should remain alert to the possibility that harm can be
p.000033: caused to both individuals and communities (Table 2).
p.000033:
p.000033: This does not mean that surveillance should not be conducted. Rather, those conducting surveillance have
p.000033: an obligation to identify potential harm beforehand, to monitor for harm during and after surveillance
p.000033: and to put in place processes to mitigate harm. Without continuous monitoring, mitigation is impos- sible.
p.000033: This is vital, not only because it is wrong to cause unnecessary harm, but also because harm – to both
p.000033: individuals and communi- ties, such as loss of property value or tourism dollars – may also damage public
...
Political / vulnerable
Searching for indicator vulnerable:
(return to top)
p.000016:
p.000016: Physicians, worried about interference with their patients and use of their time, often resented, resisted
p.000016: or simply ignored man- dates for reporting. But not all monitoring of morbidity and mortality
p.000016: required iden- tification of cases by name. Reporting of sexually transmitted diseases, for
p.000016: example, was often done by code instead of name in industrialized countries (21). Contact tracing, of course,
p.000016: required names, but most physi- cians kept the index case anonymous when patients cooperated by providing
p.000016: the names of sex partners and adhering to treatment. Whether names were necessary or whether informed
p.000016: consent was required often framed debates as surveillance was extended, over
p.000016:
p.000016: Background
p.000017: 17
p.000017:
p.000017: the course of the twentieth century, to NCDs such as cancer, diabetes and stroke and to occupational exposures,
p.000017: substance use, road accidents, injuries, vaccination status and vaccine reactions (22).
p.000017:
p.000017: During the twentieth century, it was often people affected by a disease or condition who challenged the need for
p.000017: surveillance; but, just as often, the story of surveillance has been one in which affected groups have demanded
p.000017: the “right to be counted” (22). NCD surveil- lance, in contrast to infectious disease surveil- lance, has been
p.000017: underfunded and “woefully inadequate,” even in high-income countries (23). Workers exposed to toxic hazards
p.000017: and citizens vulnerable to environmental pollut- ants have sometimes joined social movements as a means of
p.000017: gaining both attention and the resources necessary for surveillance; however, the more common story is that chronic
p.000017: disease threats, particularly those of vulnerable popu- lations, remain invisible.
p.000017: Global crises often expose systemic challenges that are insufficiently addressed. Undocu- mented migrants
p.000017: with tuberculosis are still not included in statistics submitted to WHO by some countries (24, 25), but it
p.000017: would be a mistake to assume that the only challenges are the absence of surveillance or under-reporting. Tuberculosis
p.000017: surveillance data, for instance, were critical for determining levels of funding from the Global Fund to Fight
p.000017: AIDS, Tubercu- losis and Malaria. Surveillance staff sometimes
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017: Industrial pollution. Moscow, Russia.
p.000017: Source: WHO /Sergey Volkov
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017: found themselves under high pressure to reach what some criticized as unrealistic targets. They had to choose
p.000017: between showing “good” results or losing their jobs, adversely affecting the quality of data in some settings (26, 27).
p.000017:
p.000017: These guidelines are based on the understand- ing that surveillance is so fundamental a public health practice that
p.000017: its advancement cannot depend on crises or citizen protests to make the case for tracking disease for
p.000017: the sake of public health. While these guidelines represent a call to action, it is not a call to unrestrained
p.000017: action. Rather, public health surveillance, con- ducted in a manner that anticipates ethical challenges and
p.000017: proactively seeks to reduce unnecessary risks, provides the architecture for social well-being.
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000018: 18
p.000018: Background
p.000018:
...
p.000020: following ethical consid- erations are of particular importance for public health surveillance. They represent
p.000020: the back- bone of the guidelines:
p.000020:
p.000020: Common good: Surveillance is widely acknowledged to be a public good (43), and some of the benefits
p.000020: it pro- vides cannot be subdivided into indi- vidual private benefits because they are fundamentally shared (41,
p.000020: 44). Surveil- lance is justified, fundamentally, as a requirement for the good of all. With- out adequate
p.000020: oversight by public health bodies and the participation of individ- uals and communities, the shared ben- efits of
p.000020: surveillance are at risk. There is a complex literature on economics and moral philosophy that seeks to define and
p.000020: distinguish the terms “public good”, “public goods,” and “the com- mon good” (45). After careful delibera-
p.000020: tion, the committee adopted the term “the common good” to capture the notion of public goods more
p.000020: broadly conceived than in the narrow economic sense.
p.000020: Equity: Public health ethics is centrally concerned with the idea of equity. It is well established that
p.000020: social inequality has adverse effects on health (46). Not all inequality is within human control or is
p.000020: morally relevant. Morally prob- lematic inequality is commonly referred to as inequity. A just or fair society
p.000020: will attempt to provide equitable conditions for humans to flourish, with health as a central component.
p.000020: Equity some- times requires that the most vulnerable people receive what may appear to be disproportionate
p.000020: resources: that is, the unfair distribution of risks requires addi- tional resources to balance the scales.
p.000020: Public health surveillance can further the pursuit of equity by identifying the particular problems
p.000020: of disadvantaged populations, including global communi- ties, providing the evidence for focused health campaigns
p.000020: and identifying the basis of unfair differences in health.
p.000020:
p.000020: Respect for persons: Public health eth- ics is concerned with the rights, liberty, and other interests of individuals
p.000020: as well as overall population well-being. When- ever possible, individuals should be involved in decisions
p.000020: that affect them. In some cases, individuals should be free to make their own choices; in other cases,
p.000020: when population-level interven- tions may be necessary, individuals can be consulted and involved in
p.000020: decision- making. But many individuals (such as young children) cannot make their own choices, and the State has
p.000020: an obligation to protect them and promote their long- term health interests. Undertaking pub- lic health surveillance
p.000020: is, itself, arguably an expression of respect for persons. This further requires ensuring that data about
p.000020: individuals and groups are pro- tected and risks for harm are minimized
p.000020:
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000021: 21
p.000021:
p.000021:
...
p.000024: identifiable data, including names and other socio-demo- graphic characteristics. Such intrusion on clini- cal
p.000024: confidentiality is justified when names are required to ensure the collection of accurate data, which is separate
p.000024: from the need to target interventions. But accurate data and targeted interventions both rest on the moral obligation
p.000024: to prevent harm to others and the common good or to provide the best resources to pop- ulations according to
p.000024: the burden of disease, as in the case of cancer registries. Guidelines 11 and 12 outline the ethical
p.000024: limits to name- based reporting.
p.000024:
p.000024: Public health surveillance activities require investment of societal resources to preserve, protect and
p.000024: promote health. In all countries, but especially in low-resource settings, allo- cating societal resources for
p.000024: public health sur- veillance requires prioritization. This issue is discussed further in Guideline 5.
p.000024:
p.000024: Guidelines
p.000025: 25
p.000025:
p.000025: Once surveillance data are available, Member States have the moral duty to use the data actively to promote
p.000025: better health outcomes. Even when resources limit the capacity of countries to take immediate action
p.000025: on the basis of the findings of public health surveil- lance, the data provide the evidentiary basis for
p.000025: advocacy directed at both the national
p.000025: and global communities, thus potentially empowering the most vulnerable. The pur- suit of equity
p.000025: establishes a warrant for sur- veillance, and the global community should provide the necessary help in
p.000025: moving from collecting and analysing data to action (see Guideline 6).
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
...
p.000035: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
...
Searching for indicator vulnerability:
(return to top)
p.000034: surveillance in order to minimize any negative consequences for a community and to maintain trust.
p.000034: Addition- ally, given their mission to mitigate harm, politically neutral international humanitar-
p.000034: ian organizations must not be hindered in situations such as civil conflict zones, where international
p.000034: agencies are constrained when it comes to recognizing “opposition parties as operational partners” (3).
p.000034:
p.000034: Notably, public health professionals them- selves sometimes require protection. As champions of
p.000034: the common good, they must be free to report without fear of reprisal. As surveillance officials have a
p.000034: responsibility to speak up, they should have protection. This idea is established in the IHR, which
p.000034: protects the confidentiality of those who report a veri- fiable outbreak or a public health event out- side
p.000034: official channels.
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000035: 35
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: Guideline 9. Surveillance of individuals or groups who are particularly susceptible to disease, harm or injustice is
p.000035: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: The HIV oral test on a brothel bed in Belém do Pará, Brazil.
p.000035: Source: Laura Murray
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guideline 10. Governments and others who hold surveillance data must ensure that identifiable data are appropriately
p.000036: secured.
p.000036:
p.000036: Responsible data collection and sharing prac- tices should ensure the security of the data collected in order to
p.000036: respect persons and safe- guard the privacy and other interests of the individuals and communities concerned
p.000036: (50). Every effort must be made to secure records to prevent unauthorized disclosure. Security is
p.000036: different from privacy and confidential- ity, yet it is an essential component of each. “Security” in
p.000036: this context consists of opera- tional and technological safeguards to protect personal data from unauthorized
p.000036: access or disclosure. Maintaining information security is not fool-proof, as electronic databases can be infiltrated.
p.000036:
p.000036: Governments and others who hold surveil- lance data must take appropriate techni- cal and
...
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
p.000045: preserve trust in public health surveillance systems, there should be compel- ling justification for sharing
p.000045: identifiable data for non-public health uses.
p.000045:
p.000045: Inappropriate sharing of surveillance data is especially controversial in countries in which law enforcement
p.000045: or other agencies have been
p.000045:
p.000045: implicated in systematic violations of human rights. In these contexts, collaboration with law enforcement
p.000045: agencies may undermine trust in public health surveillance, creating a disincentive for seeking care or
p.000045: honest report- ing of data. This is a particular concern for individuals or groups in situations of particular
p.000045: vulnerability (92). Further, such unwarranted sharing will potentially inflict long-term dam- age on public
p.000045: health efforts more broadly.
p.000045:
p.000045: The governance mechanisms recommended in Guideline 2 should ensure that the exceptional conditions, if any, under which
p.000045: identifiable sur- veillance data may be shared are specified and made transparent. Such a review will require
p.000045: determination of whether the threat is of suf- ficient magnitude to warrant potential damage to the integrity of and
p.000045: trust in public health sur- veillance systems. Sanctions must be in place to prevent inappropriate data-sharing
p.000045: by public health agencies and inappropriate use of data by agencies outside the public health sector.
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: WHO Immunization officers visit Quang Binh Province, Viet Nam to monitor the Measles-Rubella Immunization campaign.
p.000045: Source: WHO / WPRO /Emmanuel Eraly
p.000045:
p.000046: 46
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046: A barcode is placed at the entrance of houses. After being flashed with a smartphone, the barcode provides information
...
Health / Drug Usage
Searching for indicator drug:
(return to top)
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: WHO gratefully acknowledges the contribution of the WHO Guidelines Development Group, which shared extensive
p.000005: knowledge, original text and comments on the document. All are also co-authors of the document:
p.000005:
p.000005: Kokou Agoudavi, Ministry of Health, Togo; Jimoh Amzat, Usmanu Danfodiyo Univer- sity, Nigeria;
p.000005: Ronald Bayer, Columbia Univer- sity Mailman School of Public Health, USA; Philippe Calain, Médecins Sans
p.000005: Frontières, Switzerland; Yali Cong, Peking University Health Science Centre, China; Angus Dawson,
p.000005: University of Sydney, Australia; Claire Gayrel, University of Namur, Belgium; Jennifer L. Gibson,
p.000005: Joint Centre for Bioethics, Univer- sity of Toronto, Canada; Kenneth Goodman, University of Miami,
p.000005: USA; Vijayaprasad Gopichandran, Tamil Nadu School of Public Health, India; Einar Heldal, Institute of
p.000005: Public Health, Norway; Calvin Ho Wai Loon, National University of Singapore Centre for Biomedical Ethics, Singapore;
p.000005: Hussain Jafri, Council for Alzheimer’s, Pakistan; Lisa M. Lee, Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical
p.000005: Issues, USA; Sergio Litewka, University of Miami, USA; Mina Mobasher, Kerman University of Medical Sciences, Islamic
p.000005: Republic of Iran; Keymanthri Moodley, Stellenbosch University, South Africa; Boateng Okyere, University of Ghana,
p.000005: Ghana; Maria Consorcia Quizon, Training programs in Epidemiology and Public Health Interventions Network,
p.000005: Philippines; Pathom Sawanpany- alert, Food and Drug Administration, Thailand;
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: Acknowledgements
p.000007: 7
p.000007:
p.000007:
p.000007: Michael Selgelid, Monash University, Australia; Ross Upshur, University of Toronto, Canada; Effy Vayena,
p.000007: University of Zurich, Switzerland.
p.000007:
p.000007: The Global Network of WHO Collaborating Centres for Bioethics and their members are gratefully acknowledged.
p.000007:
p.000007: WHO thanks the support provided by various observers: Ehsan S Gooshki, Tehran University, Islamic Republic of
p.000007: Iran; Katherine Littler, Wel- come Trust, United Kingdom; Debra Mosure, Centers for Disease Control and
p.000007: Prevention, USA; Patricia Sweeney, Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, USA; and Hans van Delden,
p.000007: Utrecht University Medical Centre, Netherlands.
p.000007:
p.000007: The support and contributions of two consul- tants is greatly appreciated: Carl H. Coleman, Seton Hall Law
p.000007: School, USA, and Michele Loi, Swiss Federal Institute of Technology, Switzerland.
p.000007:
p.000007: This guidance document benefited from the work of a literature review group, comprising: Corinna Klingler,
p.000007: Ludwig Maximilian University Munich, Germany (lead); Diego S. Silva, Simon Fraser University, Canada; Daniel
p.000007: Strech and Christopher Schürmann, Hannover Medical School, Germany; and Michael Vaughn, Colum- bia University
p.000007: School of Public Health, USA.
p.000007:
p.000007: WHO’s Global Health Ethics team extends thanks to the WHO internal steering group for its invaluable
p.000007: advice on development of the guidelines: Isabel Bergeri, Marie-Charlotte Bouesseau, Somnath Chatterji, Joan
...
p.000009: by providing information about health and its determinants. It can provide an evidentiary basis
p.000009: for establishing and evaluating public health policy. Surveillance, for example, will be central to the
p.000009: achievement of the United Nation’s Sustainable Development Goals. The availability of the results of
p.000009: surveillance enables and promotes policy choice. Thus, access to surveillance information can serve as
p.000009: a tool for advocacy when the results are
p.000009:
p.000009: Table 1. Dimensions of public health surveillance
p.000009: Scope
p.000009:
p.000009: Communicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Early detecting and warning of epidemics
p.000009: Noncommunicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Trend and spatial analyses
p.000009: Environmental factors
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Risk detection
p.000009: Risk factors and risk markers
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Objectives
p.000009: Generating hypotheses
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Health system
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Monitoring of health system performance
p.000009: Demographic variables
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Evaluation of control measures
p.000009: Health-related events (e.g. food and drug safety, vaccine reactions)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Registries Case reports Repeated
p.000009: surveys
p.000009: Data collection tools
p.000009: Bio-banks Secondary data sources
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Types of analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Population-based (universal or sentinel sites)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Social media
p.000009:
p.000009: Estimation of incidence or prevalence
p.000009: Measurement of associations
p.000009: Assessment of trends
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Uses
p.000009: Assessment of spatial patterns
p.000009: Data mining
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy change
p.000009:
p.000009: Source: A.A. Haghdoost
p.000009: Structural intervention
p.000009: Case or epidemic detection
p.000009: Testing of hypotheses
p.000009: Implementation research
p.000009: Quality assurance
p.000009:
p.000010: 10
p.000010: Introduction
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010: shared with populations and policy-makers in a timely, appropriate manner.
p.000010:
p.000010: Yet surveillance has been the subject of some- times bitter controversy. Public health sur- veillance may
p.000010: limit not only privacy but also other civil liberties. For example, surveillance may trigger mandatory
p.000010: quarantine, isolation, or seizure of property during an epidemic (2). When surveillance involves
p.000010: name-based reporting (that is, reporting by name), it can, to the extent that populations are made aware, trigger
p.000010: profound concern about intrusions on privacy, discrimination, and stigmatization. Name-based reporting can also
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
...
p.000016: comprehensive surveillance systems nor for grappling with the ethical issues posed by surveillance sys-
p.000016: tems and practices. International regulation, like national law and regulation, is an impor- tant tool
p.000016: that establishes a duty to conduct surveillance while also setting limits on that practice. What is legal,
p.000016: however, is not always ethical. Ethics is an essential tool for critically evaluating law, regulation and
p.000016: practice and for addressing the value conflicts that may be posed by surveillance.
p.000016: Local and national surveillance systems emerged in the nineteenth century, and almost all comprised
p.000016: physicians’ case reports. The data were initially used almost exclusively to document either social
p.000016: progress or misery (21). At the heart of the most bitter battles over individual rights and population
p.000016: health, how- ever, were surveillance measures that made intervention at the level of individuals possible, with
p.000016: the discovery of germs and the realization that many diseases were spread from person to person. Interventions
p.000016: based on communica- ble disease reports were sometimes welcomed (leading to referral to clinics, provision of food and
p.000016: clothing) but were sometimes a cause of alarm (when leading to mandatory vaccination or treatment, quarantine or
p.000016: deportation). Offi- cial morbidity reports were usually protected against public disclosure by law,
p.000016: regulation, and practice. Surveillance was also the basis for population health measures, such as the
p.000016: pasteurization of milk, regulation of food and drug manufacture, housing reform and other measures that addressed
p.000016: the structural causes of disease. Resistance to such measures, largely on the part of independent and incor-
p.000016: porated businesses, was often framed as an issue of individual rights.
p.000016:
p.000016: Physicians, worried about interference with their patients and use of their time, often resented, resisted
p.000016: or simply ignored man- dates for reporting. But not all monitoring of morbidity and mortality
p.000016: required iden- tification of cases by name. Reporting of sexually transmitted diseases, for
p.000016: example, was often done by code instead of name in industrialized countries (21). Contact tracing, of course,
p.000016: required names, but most physi- cians kept the index case anonymous when patients cooperated by providing
p.000016: the names of sex partners and adhering to treatment. Whether names were necessary or whether informed
p.000016: consent was required often framed debates as surveillance was extended, over
p.000016:
p.000016: Background
p.000017: 17
p.000017:
p.000017: the course of the twentieth century, to NCDs such as cancer, diabetes and stroke and to occupational exposures,
p.000017: substance use, road accidents, injuries, vaccination status and vaccine reactions (22).
p.000017:
p.000017: During the twentieth century, it was often people affected by a disease or condition who challenged the need for
p.000017: surveillance; but, just as often, the story of surveillance has been one in which affected groups have demanded
...
p.000021: disease control. Building on the original “Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis preven- tion, care and
p.000021: control” in 2010 (47), the “Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB Strategy” (48) addresses
p.000021: the most critical challenges to reducing the number of deaths from tuberculosis by 95% by 2030
p.000021: and the number of new cases by 90% between 2015 and 2035. The “Guidance for managing ethical issues in
p.000021: infectious disease outbreaks” (49) in 2016, in response to the outbreak of Ebola virus disease in West Africa
p.000021: in 2014–2015, underscored the importance of providing ethics guidance beyond “a spe- cific pathogen in
p.000021: isolation” to “cross-cutting ethical issues that apply to infectious disease outbreaks generally”.
p.000021:
p.000021: The three projects obviously have important continuity. All, for example, emphasize equity, justice, and the
p.000021: common good (sometimes expressed as “stewardship” or “reciproc- ity”). All stress the importance
p.000021: of respecting the dignity of persons (sometimes emphasiz- ing autonomy or privacy). Accountability and the
p.000021: importance of good governance either explicitly or implicitly informs all three. They also have
p.000021: relevant differences that reflect the subject of each. The tuberculosis guidelines, for example, address the
p.000021: problem of drug- resistant disease and thus emphasize the harm principle. The guidelines on infectious disease
p.000021: outbreaks, framed as they were by concern for groups in conditions of tremendous vulner- ability and the ways
p.000021: in which outbreaks can become crises, further amplified by fear and distrust, places greater emphasis on
p.000021: human rights. Given the need to make decisions in
p.000021:
p.000022: 22
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: the face of uncertainty, they also stress utility, proportionality and efficacy.
p.000022:
p.000022: The ethical considerations outlined above and repeated and amplified in the guidelines that follow are, in the
p.000022: estimation of this commit- tee, central to justification of surveillance as a core activity, beyond outbreaks
p.000022: or infectious disease situations. They must be applied in situations that may vary in fundamental ways. The
p.000022: guidelines recognize that trade-offs of values are sometimes inevitable. The local tra- ditions and
p.000022: priorities in countries may some- times result in a different balance between competing values and
p.000022: priorities. It is important to stress, however, that not all trade-offs are morally acceptable. Local, national,
p.000022: or regional circumstances may be characterized by gross injustice or violations of human rights. In these
p.000022: contexts, rather than serving the common good, public health surveillance may be used as an
p.000022: instrument for violation of respect for persons, equity, and justice. In countries where sex work is a
...
p.000044: document.
p.000044:
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
p.000044: research is not appropriate for conducting public health surveillance, surveillance data should be shared only
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
...
p.000049: 17. Wesolowski A, Stresman G, Eagle N, Stevenson J, Owaga C, Marube E, et al. Quantifying travel behavior for
p.000049: infectious disease research: a comparison of data from surveys and mobile phones. Sci Rep 2014;4:5678.
p.000049: 18. Lajous M, Danon L, Lopez-Ridaura R, Astley CM, Miller JC, Dowell SF, et al. Mobile messaging as surveillance
p.000049: tool during pandemic (H1N1) 2009, Mexico. Emerg Infect Dis 2010;16:1488–1489.
p.000049: 19. International health regulations. Geneva: World Health Organization; 1983.
p.000049:
p.000050: 50
p.000050: References
p.000050:
p.000050: 20. Report of the Ebola interim assessment panel. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2016
p.000050: (http://www.who.int/csr/resources/publications/ebola/report-by-panel.pdf?ua=1, accessed 19 December 2016).
p.000050: 21. Baldwin P. Contagion and the state in Europe, 1830–1930. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1999.
p.000050: 22. Teutsch SM, Churchill RE. Principles and practice of public health surveillance. New York: Oxford University
p.000050: Press; 1994.
p.000050: 23. Pew Environmental Health Commission. Transition Report to the New Administration: Strengthen- ing Our Public
p.000050: Health Defenses Against Environmental Threats. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins School of Public Health; 2001.
p.000050: 24. Communicable diseases surveillance in Singapore 2015. Singapore: Ministry of Health; 2015.
p.000050: 25. Tuberculosis country profile 2015, Singapore. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000050: 26. Matthys F, Van der Stuyft P, Van Deun A. Universal tuberculosis control targets: not so smart. Int J Tuberc Lung
p.000050: Dis 2009;13:923–924.
p.000050: 27. Kamal SM, Hossain A, Sultana S, Begum V, Haque N, Ahmed J, et al. Anti-tuberculosis drug
p.000050: resistance in Bangladesh: reflections from the first nationwide survey. Int J Tuberc Lung Dis
p.000050: 2015;19:151–156.
p.000050: 28. Smith MJ, Silva DS. Ethics for pandemics beyond influenza: Ebola, drug-resistant tuberculosis, and anticipating
p.000050: future ethical challenges in pandemic preparedness and response. Monash Bioeth Rev 2015;33:130–147.
p.000050: 29. Lee LM, Thacker SB, St Louis ME, Teutsch SM. Principles and practice of public health surveillance. 3rd Edition.
p.000050: Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2010.
p.000050: 30. Fox RC. Advanced medical technology – social and ethical implications. Annu Rev Sociol
p.000050: 1976;2:231–268.
p.000050: 31. Fox RC, Swazey JP. Medical morality is not bioethics: medical ethics in China and the United States. New
p.000050: Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books; 1988.
p.000050: 32. Rothman JD. Strangers at the bedside: a history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making.
p.000050: New York, NY: Basic Books; 1991.
p.000050: 33. Ackerman HT. Choosing between Nuremberg and the National Commission: balancing of moral principles in clinical
p.000050: research. In: The ethics of research involving human subjects: facing the 21st century. Frederick, MD: University
p.000050: Publishing Group; 1996.
p.000050: 34. International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. Geneva; Council for Interna- tional
p.000050: Organizations of Medical Sciences; 1991.
p.000050: 35. International ethical guidelines for epidemiological studies. Geneva; Council for International
p.000050: Organizations of Medical Sciences; 2009.
p.000050: 36. Hepple B, Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Public health: ethical issues. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics;
p.000050: 2007.
...
Searching for indicator substance:
(return to top)
p.000016: deportation). Offi- cial morbidity reports were usually protected against public disclosure by law,
p.000016: regulation, and practice. Surveillance was also the basis for population health measures, such as the
p.000016: pasteurization of milk, regulation of food and drug manufacture, housing reform and other measures that addressed
p.000016: the structural causes of disease. Resistance to such measures, largely on the part of independent and incor-
p.000016: porated businesses, was often framed as an issue of individual rights.
p.000016:
p.000016: Physicians, worried about interference with their patients and use of their time, often resented, resisted
p.000016: or simply ignored man- dates for reporting. But not all monitoring of morbidity and mortality
p.000016: required iden- tification of cases by name. Reporting of sexually transmitted diseases, for
p.000016: example, was often done by code instead of name in industrialized countries (21). Contact tracing, of course,
p.000016: required names, but most physi- cians kept the index case anonymous when patients cooperated by providing
p.000016: the names of sex partners and adhering to treatment. Whether names were necessary or whether informed
p.000016: consent was required often framed debates as surveillance was extended, over
p.000016:
p.000016: Background
p.000017: 17
p.000017:
p.000017: the course of the twentieth century, to NCDs such as cancer, diabetes and stroke and to occupational exposures,
p.000017: substance use, road accidents, injuries, vaccination status and vaccine reactions (22).
p.000017:
p.000017: During the twentieth century, it was often people affected by a disease or condition who challenged the need for
p.000017: surveillance; but, just as often, the story of surveillance has been one in which affected groups have demanded
p.000017: the “right to be counted” (22). NCD surveil- lance, in contrast to infectious disease surveil- lance, has been
p.000017: underfunded and “woefully inadequate,” even in high-income countries (23). Workers exposed to toxic hazards
p.000017: and citizens vulnerable to environmental pollut- ants have sometimes joined social movements as a means of
p.000017: gaining both attention and the resources necessary for surveillance; however, the more common story is that chronic
p.000017: disease threats, particularly those of vulnerable popu- lations, remain invisible.
p.000017: Global crises often expose systemic challenges that are insufficiently addressed. Undocu- mented migrants
p.000017: with tuberculosis are still not included in statistics submitted to WHO by some countries (24, 25), but it
p.000017: would be a mistake to assume that the only challenges are the absence of surveillance or under-reporting. Tuberculosis
p.000017: surveillance data, for instance, were critical for determining levels of funding from the Global Fund to Fight
p.000017: AIDS, Tubercu- losis and Malaria. Surveillance staff sometimes
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017: Industrial pollution. Moscow, Russia.
p.000017: Source: WHO /Sergey Volkov
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
...
p.000053: 83. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000053: 84. Bernstein AB, Sweeney MH. Public health surveillance data: legal, policy, ethical, regulatory, and practical
p.000053: issues. MMWR Suppl 2012;61:30–34.
p.000053: 85. Klingler C, Silva D, Schuermann C, Reis A, Saxena A, Strech D. Ethical issues in public health sur- veillance: a
p.000053: systematic review. BMC Public Health 2017; 4:17(1): 295
p.000053: 86. Dye C, Bartolomeos K, Moorthy V, Kieny MP. Data sharing in public health emergencies: a call to researchers.
p.000053: Bull World Health Organ 2016;94:158.
p.000053: 87. Langat P, Pisartchik D, Silva D, Bernard C, Olsen K, Smith M, et al. Is there a duty to share? Eth- ics of
p.000053: sharing research data in the context of public health emergencies. Public Health Ethics 2011;4:4–11.
p.000053: 88. Hripcsak G, Bloomrosen M, Flately Brennan P, Chute CG, Cimino J, Detmer DE, et al. Health data use,
p.000053: stewardship, and governance: ongoing gaps and challenges: a report from AMIA’s 2012 health policy meeting. J
p.000053: Am Med Inform Assoc 2014;21:204–211.
p.000053: 89. Geissbuhler A, Safran C, Buchan I, Bellazzi R, Labkoff S, Eilenberg K. Trustworthy reuse of health data: a
p.000053: transnational perspective. Int J Med Inform 2013;82:1–9.
p.000053: 90. Longo LD, Drazen MJ. Data sharing. N Engl J Med 2016;374:276–277.
p.000053: 91. Frakt AB, Bagley N. Protection or harm? Suppressing substance-use data. N Engl J Med
p.000053: 2015;372:1879–1881.
p.000053: 92. Sidel VW, Cohen HW, Gould RM. Good intentions and the road to bioterrorism preparedness. Am J Public Health
p.000053: 2001;91:716–718.
p.000053: 93. Fatima R, Harris RJ, Enarson DA, Hinderaker SG, Qadeer E, Ali K, et al. Estimating tuberculosis
p.000053: burden and case detection in Pakistan. Int J Tuberc Lung Dis 2014;18:55–60.
p.000053: 94. i-IHS. Fighting Ebola using drones. 2014 (http://i-hls.com/archives/40511).
p.000053: 95. Atherton KD. The week in drones: drones fight Ebola, Iranian dogfighters, and more. Keeping up with the droneses.
p.000053: Popular Science, 26 September 2014.
p.000053: 96. Thermal imaging cameras fighting the war on Ebola virus. Las Vegas, NV: Sierra Pacific Innova-
p.000053: tions; 2014 (https://www.x20.org/thermal-imaging-cameras-war-ebola/).
p.000053: 97. Kristin BS. African drone stories. Behemoth J Civilisation 2015;8:73–96.
p.000053:
p.000053:
p.000054: 54
p.000054: References
p.000054:
p.000054: 98. Metcalf J, Keller E, Boyd D. Perspectives on big data, ethics, and society. Council for Big
p.000054: Data, Ethics and Society; 2016 (http://bdes.datasociety.net/wp-content/uploads/2016/05/Perspectives-
p.000054: on-Big-Data.pdf).
p.000054: 99. Vayena E, Salathe M, Madoff LC, Brownstein JS. Ethical challenges of big data in public health. PLoS Comput Biol
p.000054: 2015;11:e1003904.
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
p.000054:
...
Health / HIV/AIDS
Searching for indicator HIV:
(return to top)
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy change
p.000009:
p.000009: Source: A.A. Haghdoost
p.000009: Structural intervention
p.000009: Case or epidemic detection
p.000009: Testing of hypotheses
p.000009: Implementation research
p.000009: Quality assurance
p.000009:
p.000010: 10
p.000010: Introduction
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010: shared with populations and policy-makers in a timely, appropriate manner.
p.000010:
p.000010: Yet surveillance has been the subject of some- times bitter controversy. Public health sur- veillance may
p.000010: limit not only privacy but also other civil liberties. For example, surveillance may trigger mandatory
p.000010: quarantine, isolation, or seizure of property during an epidemic (2). When surveillance involves
p.000010: name-based reporting (that is, reporting by name), it can, to the extent that populations are made aware, trigger
p.000010: profound concern about intrusions on privacy, discrimination, and stigmatization. Name-based reporting can also
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
p.000010: when a public health crisis becomes a “threat to international peace and security” does surveillance become a
...
p.000021: outbreaks, framed as they were by concern for groups in conditions of tremendous vulner- ability and the ways
p.000021: in which outbreaks can become crises, further amplified by fear and distrust, places greater emphasis on
p.000021: human rights. Given the need to make decisions in
p.000021:
p.000022: 22
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: the face of uncertainty, they also stress utility, proportionality and efficacy.
p.000022:
p.000022: The ethical considerations outlined above and repeated and amplified in the guidelines that follow are, in the
p.000022: estimation of this commit- tee, central to justification of surveillance as a core activity, beyond outbreaks
p.000022: or infectious disease situations. They must be applied in situations that may vary in fundamental ways. The
p.000022: guidelines recognize that trade-offs of values are sometimes inevitable. The local tra- ditions and
p.000022: priorities in countries may some- times result in a different balance between competing values and
p.000022: priorities. It is important to stress, however, that not all trade-offs are morally acceptable. Local, national,
p.000022: or regional circumstances may be characterized by gross injustice or violations of human rights. In these
p.000022: contexts, rather than serving the common good, public health surveillance may be used as an
p.000022: instrument for violation of respect for persons, equity, and justice. In countries where sex work is a
p.000022: criminal offense, for example, HIV surveillance can be used for oppression.
p.000022: Likewise, an occupational disease surveil- lance system that results in routine dismissal of workers
p.000022: affected by silicosis, black lung, or asbestosis would be unacceptable. Appeal to “trade-offs” under such
p.000022: circumstances could well be a pretext for further oppression and should be guarded against.
p.000022:
p.000022: The State is a source of both intrusion and protection. Some disease burdens and forms of health
p.000022: oppression simply cannot be made visible without State-sponsored surveillance (50). On the one hand,
p.000022: surveillance makes public health interventions to address inequi- ties possible. On the other hand,
p.000022: surveillance may be used to impose additional burdens on those who are already disadvantaged. The only assurance
p.000022: that surveillance will amount to neither privilege nor punishment is atten- tion to the ethical
p.000022: considerations described above: both burdens and benefits should be critically weighed and then fairly
p.000022: distributed in a transparent manner in which States are held accountable.
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000023: 23
p.000023:
p.000023: IV. Guidelines
p.000023: As a consequence of the development of ethi- cal norms for the conduct of research during the past few
...
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
p.000026: include: collecting data elements that reveal stigmatized behaviour; adding new elements of data collection, such
p.000026: as measurements of CD4 counts as part of routine HIV/AIDS surveillance; adopting new uses for existing
p.000026: surveillance data, such as for case management or contact tracing; or using public health surveillance data for
p.000026: commercial or security purposes.
p.000026:
p.000026: In the case of research, review committees monitor adherence to ethics standards. Such an independent,
p.000026: impartial oversight mecha- nism allows for close scrutiny and can ensure that relevant protection is
p.000026: in place. These guidelines do not recommend mechanisms that mirror those that have emerged in the
p.000026: context of research ethics. However, public health surveillance is currently not subject to routine
p.000026: oversight. It is the obligation of coun- tries to decide the most appropriate processes for identifying and
p.000026: addressing the ethical issues that arise in public health surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Box 1 provides some examples of existing mechanisms. Any mechanism or process should ensure
p.000026: ethical implementation of sur- veillance without itself becoming an obstacle to achieving the larger public
p.000026: health goal. (We address the nexus of surveillance and research in Guideline 16.)
p.000026: Such mechanisms of ethical oversight should effectively identify the risks and ben- efits of
p.000026: surveillance and suggest measures to enhance the benefits, minimize the risks and ensure appropriate
p.000026: weighing of the com- mon good, equity, and respect for persons. Oversight should be continuous, and any
...
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: The HIV oral test on a brothel bed in Belém do Pará, Brazil.
p.000035: Source: Laura Murray
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guideline 10. Governments and others who hold surveillance data must ensure that identifiable data are appropriately
p.000036: secured.
p.000036:
p.000036: Responsible data collection and sharing prac- tices should ensure the security of the data collected in order to
p.000036: respect persons and safe- guard the privacy and other interests of the individuals and communities concerned
p.000036: (50). Every effort must be made to secure records to prevent unauthorized disclosure. Security is
p.000036: different from privacy and confidential- ity, yet it is an essential component of each. “Security” in
p.000036: this context consists of opera- tional and technological safeguards to protect personal data from unauthorized
p.000036: access or disclosure. Maintaining information security is not fool-proof, as electronic databases can be infiltrated.
p.000036:
p.000036: Governments and others who hold surveil- lance data must take appropriate techni- cal and
p.000036: organizational steps to protect data
p.000036: against accidental or unauthorized access, destruction, loss, use or disclosure, whether the data are
p.000036: collected and stored in paper or electronic (digital) format. All personnel with access to public
...
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Staff at the Medical Records Office sort through patient files at Karapitayam Hospital, Galle.
p.000036: Source: WHO / SEARO /Gary Hampton
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000037: 37
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037: Guideline 11. Under certain circumstances, the collection of names or identifiable data is justified.
p.000037:
p.000037: In some instances, the collection of names or identifiable data is both technically and ethically
p.000037: imperative. Effective surveillance may require the de-duplication of records (that is, avoidance of
p.000037: double-counting, which can lead to overestimates of incidence or prevalence).
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037: Names and addresses of people with dread diseases were regularly reported in newspapers until the 1960s.
p.000037: Source: New York Times, July 22, 1916. Public Domain.
p.000037:
p.000037: Names and other unique identifiers (social security numbers, identity card numbers) may also be
p.000037: essential for longitudinal surveil- lance registers, which require correct linkage of records on the same
p.000037: individual and/or their relatives or contacts over time. Unique identi- fiers may likewise be required to link data from
p.000037: different sources (for example, registries of tuberculosis and HIV, or birth defects and Zika virus
p.000037: infection). Critically, names and other specific identifiers are required for outbreak investigation or
p.000037: case follow-up and contact tracing (e.g. to identify and offer testing and treatment to the sexual and
p.000037: needle-sharing partners of people with sexually transmitted infections).
p.000037:
p.000037: There has been disagreement over whether unique identifiers can be used instead of names. Unique
p.000037: identifiers are expensive to cre- ate and, if constructed in a fashion that allows accurate data linkage, could
p.000037: easily be linked back to names. Some countries experimented with coded reporting for HIV infection before ultimately
p.000037: adopting nominative systems. While such systems were initially the only politically viable solution, they were
p.000037: abandoned when they were found not to meet federal funding standards for reliability and validity. However,
p.000037: technological advances have created new possibilities. Digital data can be scrambled and encrypted
p.000037: into unique identifiers that are perhaps impossible to trace back to individu- als. Good governance requires that
p.000037: the trade- offs of using names as opposed to unique identifiers or encryption be the subject of
p.000037: continuing, transparent, public discussion that takes into account surveillance system require- ments, changing
p.000037: technical capacity, risks, and evolving norms with regard to unique identi- fiers (which may become ubiquitous)
p.000037: and their legitimate use (75).
p.000037:
p.000037: Another important consideration in the col- lection of data is the geographical location of
p.000037:
p.000038: 38
p.000038: Guidelines
p.000038:
p.000038:
p.000038:
p.000038: individuals, which can be an indirect identifier. It is ethically important to prioritize confidenti- ality during the
p.000038: collection of geolocation data and also for the release or sharing of global positioning system data,
p.000038: which should be geo-masked to minimize risk of disclosure, pre- serving spatial distribution but preventing iden-
p.000038: tification of cluster-exact geo-coordinates (76).
p.000038: When the collection of names or unique identifiers is considered imperative, this requirement
...
p.000040:
p.000040: The communication of knowledge is a double- edged sword: on the one hand, knowledge may clearly empower; on
p.000040: the other, it may lead to injury, stigmatization or discrimination. A decision not to broadly publish data
p.000040: might be justified in exceptional circumstances, when doing so might cause significant harm. Likewise,
p.000040: if the affected population is so small (for example, cases of very rare cancers) that identification of
p.000040: individuals, however inadver- tent, might be inevitable, communication can be limited to preserve privacy (79).
p.000040:
p.000040: Decision-makers must also weigh the harm that could result if affected communities are not informed and
p.000040: thus deprived of knowl- edge and the ability to take action to reduce the risks and the capacity to
p.000040: engage in advo- cacy (see Guideline 13). Those responsible for public health have an affirmative duty to miti- gate
p.000040: the burdens that communication might impose on individuals or groups that are more susceptible to harm or
p.000040: injustice.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is continuing debate about when, if ever, those responsible for the design and conduct of
p.000040: surveillance are ethically obliged to inform the subjects of surveillance about individual results or
p.000040: diagnosis and then refer them to the appropriate service (80). For example, in the early days of the
p.000040: HIV epidemic, when treatment was not avail- able, blinded seroprevalence studies were considered
p.000040: ethically acceptable. In these population-based surveys, HIV status was
p.000040:
p.000040: Guidelines
p.000041: 41
p.000041:
p.000041: not communicated to the study participants. With advances in HIV diagnosis and manage- ment, however, the ethical
p.000041: consensus shifted (81). Guidelines now recommend that sur- veillance systems report results back to con-
p.000041: senting individuals (80, 82, 83). Guidelines also recommend that, after returning results to individuals,
p.000041: those with positive results be referred for proper clinical evaluation, treat- ment and follow-up at
p.000041: nearby health facili- ties. The guidelines also encourage partner testing (76) and referral for
p.000041: psychosocial
p.000041: support. This example underscores the importance of surveillance systems having an engaged
p.000041: oversight body to deal with such issues and make changes on the basis of new evidence or emerging best practices in
p.000041: other jurisdictions (Guideline 2).
p.000041: Relevant ethical considerations in making a judgement about returning information to individuals include
p.000041: feasibility, the possibility of taking action and the potential benefit to the individual.
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041: Map of parasitic disease epidemic area in China at the National Institute of Parasitic Diseases in
p.000041: Shanghai, China. 16 May 2010.
p.000041: Source: WHO / TDR /Simon Lim
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000042: 42
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guideline 14. With appropriate safeguards and justification, those responsible
p.000042: for public health surveillance have an obligation to share data with other national and international public health
p.000042: agencies.
p.000042:
p.000042: For a public health surveillance system to be effective, equitable, and promote the com- mon good, it must
p.000042: be capable of receiving and linking data from public agencies responsible for public health. For example, because
p.000042: of the stringent data security that has surrounded HIV surveillance, there have been situations in which data on
p.000042: HIV status have not been shared with those responsible for tuberculosis surveil- lance, obviating systematic
p.000042: identification of cases with co-infection. Public health work- ers cannot respond appropriately to swiftly
p.000042: changing infectious diseases in real time or take appropriate action in the case of chronic conditions without
p.000042: access to appropriate data. The same is true of occupational exposures. There have been examples in which
p.000042: agencies responsible for tracking occupational diseases have not shared data (despite the absence of a
p.000042: prohibition) with agencies responsible for
p.000042: worker protection and workplace regulation (23). A review of the literature indicated that much of the
p.000042: failure to share information is due to poor planning rather than safety concerns. Programmes have experienced
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
...
p.000047: surveillance mean that any set of ethical guidelines must cross boundaries – not only national boundaries
p.000047: but lines that have traditionally separated the public from the private (93).
p.000047:
p.000047: The problem of blurred boundaries has become even more complicated in the era of big data. By
p.000047: “big data”, we refer to both the increased volume of data that can now be col- lected and stored, usually in digital
p.000047: form, and the computational power available to pro- cess it rapidly. The ubiquitous use of personal
p.000047: computers, smartphones, wearable devices, closed-circuit cameras, genetic sequencers, semi-autonomous
p.000047: drones, and other technol- ogies means that we produce a steady stream of digital data.
p.000047:
p.000047: A data-centric technological revolution has generated great enthusiasm about the emerg- ing potential
p.000047: benefits of mining electronic health records, genomic data and other biolog- ical materials, social media
p.000047: communications, satellite imagery and other digital datasets to identify emerging disease threats,
p.000047: interrupt foodborne disease outbreaks and improve col- laboration among public health organizations. Drones have been
p.000047: hailed as a “game changer” in disease surveillance. Some have argued that
p.000047:
p.000047: drones could uniquely pinpoint an outbreak by identifying a rapid population exodus from a disease zone
p.000047: (94-96). Others are scepti- cal about “drone utopianism”, arguing that drone surveillance should not be a
p.000047: health pri- ority for countries with limited resources (97).
p.000047:
p.000047: Other new technologies, such as phylogenetic analysis of HIV, hold similar promise and peril, involving
p.000047: both use and failure to use data. Indi- viduals who generate information through per- sonal devices are probably
p.000047: unaware of the range of potential subsequent uses of their data. It is unclear whether the private sector has an obli-
p.000047: gation to share those data with public health or government officials. Custodians of such data should be aware
p.000047: of the issues that could arise and be involved in discussions about legitimate data-sharing and the steps that
p.000047: should be taken to monitor risk and prevent harm.
p.000047:
p.000047: There have been mounting calls for addi- tional research and ethical analysis on issues related to
p.000047: big data (98). The place of big data and digital disease detection in the public health
p.000047: surveillance landscape remains undetermined, and additional work should be done on privacy and anonymity, the
p.000047: inte- gration of public and private data sets and issues of data validity and reliability (99). The Deputy
p.000047: Director for Surveillance and Epide- miology at the Bill & Melinda Gates Foun- dation recently sounded an
p.000047: important call: “We need ethicists to be working on some of these problems.”
p.000047:
p.000047: In order to remain proactive rather than reac- tive, addressing these issues must represent the next frontier.
p.000047: While these guidelines are a place to start in addressing issues at the inter- section of surveillance and big data,
p.000047: the chal- lenges of this swiftly changing environment should be subject to continuing analysis and ethical
p.000047: monitoring. This challenge must be taken up by the global community.
p.000047:
...
p.002008: health studies ethical? Dissolving the boundary between research and practice. BMC Med Ethics 2014;15:61.
p.002008: 53. Graham J, Amos B, Plumptre T. Principles for Good Governance in the 21st Century: Policy Brief
p.002008: No. 15. Ottawa: Institute on Governance, 1993. Available at: http://iog.ca/wp-content/
p.002008: uploads/2012/12/2003_August_policybrief151.pdf
p.002008: 54. United Nations Development Programme. Chapter 8: Governance Principles, Institutional Capac- ity, and Quality.
p.002008: In Towards human resilience: sustaining MDG progress in an age of economic uncertainty. New York: United
p.002008: Nations Development Programme, 2011. Available at: http://www.
p.002008: undp.org/content/undp/en/home/librarypage/poverty-reduction/inclusive_development/towards_
p.002008: human_resiliencesustainingmdgprogressinanageofeconomicun.html54.
p.002008: 55. Expert information. Tokyo: Japan Ministry of Health, Labour and Welfare (http://www.mhlw.go.jp/
p.002008: bunya/kenkou/kekkaku-kansenshou11/dl/01_kansensho.pdf).
p.002008:
p.002008:
p.000052: 52
p.000052: References
p.000052:
p.000052: 56. German RR, Lee LM, Horan JM, Milstein RL, Pertowski CA, Waller MN, et al. Updated guidelines for evaluating
p.000052: public health surveillance systems: recommendations from the Guidelines Working Group. MMWR Recomm Rep 2001;50:1-35;
p.000052: quiz CE1-7.
p.000052: 57. Brock DW, Wikler D. Ethical challenges in long-term funding for HIV/AIDS. Health Aff (Millwood)
p.000052: 2009;28:1666–1676.
p.000052: 58. Daniels N. Accountability for reasonableness: establishing a fair process for priority setting is easier than
p.000052: agreeing on principles. BMJ 2000;321:1300–1301.
p.000052: 59. O’Neill O. Trust, trustworthiness and transparency. Brussels: European Foundation Centre; 2015.
p.000052: 60. WHO framework convention on tobacco control. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2003.
p.000052: 61. United Nations framework convention on climate change. New York, NY: United Nations; 2015.
p.000052: 62. Calain P. From the field side of the binoculars: a different view on global public health surveillance. Health
p.000052: Policy Plan 2007;22:13–20.
p.000052: 63. Gostin L, Friedman EA. Ebola: a crisis in global health leadership. Lancet 2014;384:1323–1325.
p.000052: 64. Bioethics for Every Generation: The Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues
p.000052: [Available from: https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/5678.html]
p.000052: 65. Guide to Democratic Deliberation for Public Health Professionals. Presidential Commission for the Study of
p.000052: Bioethical Issues; 2016.
p.000052: 66. Deliberative Scenarios: Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues; 2016 [Available from:
p.000052: https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/5707.html]
p.000052: 67. World Wide Views On Climate And Energy Results Report, World Wide Views on Cli- mate
p.000052: and Energy; 2015. [Available from: http://climateandenergy.wwviews.org/wp-content/
p.000052: uploads/2015/09/WWviews-Result-Report_english_low.pdf]
p.000052: 68. Use of quarantine to prevent transmission of severe acute respiratory syndrome. Morbid Mortal Wkly Rep
p.000052: 2003;52:680–683.
p.000052: 69. Gostin LO, Bayer R, Fairchild LA. Ethical and legal implications posed by severe acute respira-
p.000052: tory syndrome: implications for the control of severe infectious disease threats. J Am Med Assoc 2003;290:3229–3237.
p.000052: 70. MacQueen KM, McLellan E, Metzger DS, Kegeles S, Strauss RP, Scotti R, et al. What is community? An
p.000052: evidence-based definition for participatory public health. Am J Public Health 2001;91:1929–1938.
p.000052: 71. Tindana PO, Singh JA, Tracy CS, Upshur RE, Daar AS, Singer PA, et al. Grand challenges in global health:
p.000052: community engagement in research in developing countries. PLoS Med 2007;4:e273.
p.000052: 72. Zakus JD, Lysack CL. Revisiting community participation. Health Policy Plan 1998;13:1–12.
p.000052: 73. Graeme L, Stevens L, Jones KH, Dobbs C. A review of evidence relating to harm resulting from
p.000052: uses of health and biomedical data. Oxford: Nuffield Council on Bioethics; 2015.
p.000052: 74. Barrett DH, Ortmann LH, Dawson A, Saenz C, Reis A, Bolan G. Public health ethics: cases spanning the globe.
p.000052: Springer Open; 2016.
p.000052: 75. Considerations and guidance for countries adopting national health identifiers. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2014
p.000052: (http://www.unaids.org/sites/default/files/media_asset/JC2640_nationalhealthidentifiers_ en.pdf).
p.000052: 76. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000052:
p.000052: References
p.000053: 53
p.000053:
p.000053: 77. Rose G. Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol 1985;14:32–38.
p.000053: 78. Upshur RE, Morin B, Goel V. The privacy paradox: laying Orwell’s ghost to rest. Can Med Assoc J
p.000053: 2001;165:307–309.
p.000053: 79. Davison WL, Kelley RA. ICES report – 2014 prescribed entity review. Toronto, Ontario: Institute for Clinical
p.000053: Evaluative Sciences; 2014.
p.000053: 80. Baggaley R, Johnson C, Garcia Calleja JM, Sabin K, Obermeyer C, Taegtmeyer M, et al. Routine feedback of test
p.000053: results to participants in clinic- and survey-based surveillance of HIV. Bull World Health Organ 2015;93:352–355.
p.000053: 81. Fairchild LA, Ronald. Unlinked anonymous testing for HIV in developing countries: a new ethical consensus.
p.000053: Public Health Rep 2012;127:115–118.
p.000053: 82. Consolidated guidelines on HIV testing services. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000053: 83. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000053: 84. Bernstein AB, Sweeney MH. Public health surveillance data: legal, policy, ethical, regulatory, and practical
p.000053: issues. MMWR Suppl 2012;61:30–34.
p.000053: 85. Klingler C, Silva D, Schuermann C, Reis A, Saxena A, Strech D. Ethical issues in public health sur- veillance: a
p.000053: systematic review. BMC Public Health 2017; 4:17(1): 295
p.000053: 86. Dye C, Bartolomeos K, Moorthy V, Kieny MP. Data sharing in public health emergencies: a call to researchers.
p.000053: Bull World Health Organ 2016;94:158.
p.000053: 87. Langat P, Pisartchik D, Silva D, Bernard C, Olsen K, Smith M, et al. Is there a duty to share? Eth- ics of
p.000053: sharing research data in the context of public health emergencies. Public Health Ethics 2011;4:4–11.
p.000053: 88. Hripcsak G, Bloomrosen M, Flately Brennan P, Chute CG, Cimino J, Detmer DE, et al. Health data use,
p.000053: stewardship, and governance: ongoing gaps and challenges: a report from AMIA’s 2012 health policy meeting. J
p.000053: Am Med Inform Assoc 2014;21:204–211.
p.000053: 89. Geissbuhler A, Safran C, Buchan I, Bellazzi R, Labkoff S, Eilenberg K. Trustworthy reuse of health data: a
p.000053: transnational perspective. Int J Med Inform 2013;82:1–9.
p.000053: 90. Longo LD, Drazen MJ. Data sharing. N Engl J Med 2016;374:276–277.
p.000053: 91. Frakt AB, Bagley N. Protection or harm? Suppressing substance-use data. N Engl J Med
p.000053: 2015;372:1879–1881.
...
Searching for indicator hiv/aids:
(return to top)
Health / Healthy People
Searching for indicator volunteers:
(return to top)
p.000039:
p.000039: Whether or not consent is sought, informa- tion about the nature and purpose of surveil- lance and about any risk
p.000039: for harm should be publicly accessible (see Guideline 13). Rel- evant protection and adequate governance
p.000039: mechanisms (Guideline 2 and the discussion on good governance in section III), appropri- ate ethics training
p.000039: (guidelines 2 and 6) and data security (Guideline 10) will enhance trust in surveillance systems
p.000039: and ensure protection.
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000040: 40
p.000040: Guidelines
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040: Guideline 13. Results of surveillance must be effectively communicated to relevant target audiences.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is compelling, widely accepted moral justification for dissemination of the results of surveillance to
p.000040: relevant target audiences, although it is not a substitute for ameliora- tive action on the part of those
p.000040: responsible for surveillance. At the local level, relevant target audiences include the community, community officials
p.000040: and opinion leaders, health care pro- viders (doctors, nurses, health care workers), policy-makers, health
p.000040: advocates and health volunteers. The relevant target audiences may also include Member States, national
p.000040: and international agencies, and NGOs.
p.000040:
p.000040: Although CIOMS guidelines are focused on research, they stress the importance of communicating
p.000040: results, both positive and negative, to “promote and enhance pub- lic discussion”. Without
p.000040: dissemination, the social value of the work cannot be realized. In the absence of appropriate
p.000040: dissemination, those who collect data, including surveillance data, might rightly be accused of exploiting the
p.000040: individuals and groups whose health data they collect and analyse in the name of the common good. The
p.000040: Nuffield Council on Bio- ethics argued that, for dissemination to be considered appropriate, those from
p.000040: whom data are collected should understand the implications of the results for both health care and prevention
p.000040: (35).
p.000040:
p.000040: Surveillance findings should be communicated concisely in a way that is understandable to a lay audience and
p.000040: sensitive to community concerns (see Guideline 7). Communica- tion should not seed panic but alert
p.000040: people to relevant risks in a sensible manner. Mass mailings, toll-free information hotlines, social media,
p.000040: newspapers, seminars, and public meetings are all possible means for conveying
p.000040: surveillance information to the communities from which data were collected and analysed and to the public.
p.000040: In resource-limited set- tings, street theatre, and folk art and other community-based methods can be
...
Health / Physically Ill
Searching for indicator sick:
(return to top)
p.000033: responsible for conduct- ing surveillance should remain alert to the possibility that harm can be
p.000033: caused to both individuals and communities (Table 2).
p.000033:
p.000033: This does not mean that surveillance should not be conducted. Rather, those conducting surveillance have
p.000033: an obligation to identify potential harm beforehand, to monitor for harm during and after surveillance
p.000033: and to put in place processes to mitigate harm. Without continuous monitoring, mitigation is impos- sible.
p.000033: This is vital, not only because it is wrong to cause unnecessary harm, but also because harm – to both
p.000033: individuals and communi- ties, such as loss of property value or tourism dollars – may also damage public
p.000033: trust in the programme and in public health in general. (See guidelines 5, 12 and 13 and the discus-
p.000033: sion of good governance in section III.)
p.000033:
p.000033: In some instances, countries have provided compensation for the harm that might
p.000033:
p.000033: inevitably accompany surveillance. In the con- text of SARS, Chinese Taipei gave people who were quarantined the
p.000033: equivalent of US$ 147 (68). Basic welfare benefits or sick pay for those deprived of work as a result
p.000033: of surveil- lance are other possibilities. The possibility of compensation should not, however, pose a
p.000033: barrier to surveillance (69).
p.000033:
p.000033: There are many different types of harm: eco- nomic, legal, psychological, social (and reputa- tional) and
p.000033: physical. All should be considered in relation to surveillance (70-72). For example, a migrant or a person in another
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
...
p.000052: 2003;52:680–683.
p.000052: 69. Gostin LO, Bayer R, Fairchild LA. Ethical and legal implications posed by severe acute respira-
p.000052: tory syndrome: implications for the control of severe infectious disease threats. J Am Med Assoc 2003;290:3229–3237.
p.000052: 70. MacQueen KM, McLellan E, Metzger DS, Kegeles S, Strauss RP, Scotti R, et al. What is community? An
p.000052: evidence-based definition for participatory public health. Am J Public Health 2001;91:1929–1938.
p.000052: 71. Tindana PO, Singh JA, Tracy CS, Upshur RE, Daar AS, Singer PA, et al. Grand challenges in global health:
p.000052: community engagement in research in developing countries. PLoS Med 2007;4:e273.
p.000052: 72. Zakus JD, Lysack CL. Revisiting community participation. Health Policy Plan 1998;13:1–12.
p.000052: 73. Graeme L, Stevens L, Jones KH, Dobbs C. A review of evidence relating to harm resulting from
p.000052: uses of health and biomedical data. Oxford: Nuffield Council on Bioethics; 2015.
p.000052: 74. Barrett DH, Ortmann LH, Dawson A, Saenz C, Reis A, Bolan G. Public health ethics: cases spanning the globe.
p.000052: Springer Open; 2016.
p.000052: 75. Considerations and guidance for countries adopting national health identifiers. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2014
p.000052: (http://www.unaids.org/sites/default/files/media_asset/JC2640_nationalhealthidentifiers_ en.pdf).
p.000052: 76. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000052:
p.000052: References
p.000053: 53
p.000053:
p.000053: 77. Rose G. Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol 1985;14:32–38.
p.000053: 78. Upshur RE, Morin B, Goel V. The privacy paradox: laying Orwell’s ghost to rest. Can Med Assoc J
p.000053: 2001;165:307–309.
p.000053: 79. Davison WL, Kelley RA. ICES report – 2014 prescribed entity review. Toronto, Ontario: Institute for Clinical
p.000053: Evaluative Sciences; 2014.
p.000053: 80. Baggaley R, Johnson C, Garcia Calleja JM, Sabin K, Obermeyer C, Taegtmeyer M, et al. Routine feedback of test
p.000053: results to participants in clinic- and survey-based surveillance of HIV. Bull World Health Organ 2015;93:352–355.
p.000053: 81. Fairchild LA, Ronald. Unlinked anonymous testing for HIV in developing countries: a new ethical consensus.
p.000053: Public Health Rep 2012;127:115–118.
p.000053: 82. Consolidated guidelines on HIV testing services. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000053: 83. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000053: 84. Bernstein AB, Sweeney MH. Public health surveillance data: legal, policy, ethical, regulatory, and practical
p.000053: issues. MMWR Suppl 2012;61:30–34.
p.000053: 85. Klingler C, Silva D, Schuermann C, Reis A, Saxena A, Strech D. Ethical issues in public health sur- veillance: a
p.000053: systematic review. BMC Public Health 2017; 4:17(1): 295
p.000053: 86. Dye C, Bartolomeos K, Moorthy V, Kieny MP. Data sharing in public health emergencies: a call to researchers.
p.000053: Bull World Health Organ 2016;94:158.
...
Health / patients in emergency situations
Searching for indicator emergencies:
(return to top)
p.000018: “groups” of people. After considerable controversy, a con- sensus emerged: CIOMS stressed the impor- tance of
p.000018: the principles of research ethics first set out in the Nuremberg Code but recognized that application in the
p.000018: epidemiological context would require flexibility (34). The tradition that developed was one in
p.000018: which research
p.000018:
p.000018: ethics committees could waive a requirement for informed consent when the risk posed by epidemiological
p.000018: research was “no more than minimal” and obtaining consent would make the research “impracticable” (34).
p.000018:
p.000018: While public health surveillance may share methodological strategies with epidemiologi- cal research, it is
p.000018: not simply another form of research. In surveillance a community is the subject of concern. That surveillance
p.000018: is one of the responsibilities of public health was rec- ognized in 1991 by CIOMS, which described
p.000018: surveillance in emergency outbreak situations as clearly requiring exemption from ethi- cal review and
p.000018: oversight. In dire situations, surveillance could not “await the formal approval of an ethical
p.000018: review committee” (34). Emergencies, however, accounted for only a small part of surveillance activities.
p.000018:
p.000018: Not until its 2009 revision did CIOMS guide- lines explicitly support continuous case-based public health
p.000018: surveillance (in the absence of informed consent). The revision stated, “Several considerations
p.000018: support the com- mon practice of requiring that all practitio- ners submit relevant data [to public
p.000018: health surveillance registries]: the importance of having comprehensive information … about an entire
p.000018: population, the scientific need to include all cases in order to avoid undetect- able selection bias and
p.000018: the general ethical principle that burdens and benefits should be distributed across the population.” (35)
p.000018: This position echoed that of the Nuffield Council on Bioethics in the United Kingdom. In 2007, the Council
p.000018: warned against allowing individuals to opt out of reporting, arguing, “We are aware of several examples [in
p.000018: which] consent requirements have or could have had serious negative consequences.” (36) Despite this sweeping
p.000018: endorsement of mandatory nominative case reporting without consent, the Council underscored the
p.000018: inevitability of
p.000018:
p.000018: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000019: 19
p.000019:
p.000019: making ethical judgements about the limits of surveillance (36).
...
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
p.000042: re-shared by other agencies, except under the conditions specified elsewhere in this document, e.g. in
p.000042: guidelines 16–17. When the protection of different datasets is not equivalent, the more stringent
p.000042: privacy standard should be applied.
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000043: 43
p.000043:
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties involved in surveillance share data
p.000043: in a timely fashion.
p.000043: The collection and sharing of data are essen- tial activities in ordinary public health practice. During
p.000043: emergencies, data-sharing takes on increased importance because of the urgency of the situation,
p.000043: uncertainty in the face of incomplete or changing information, the com- promised response capacity of local health
p.000043: sys- tems and the heightened role of cross-border collaboration. For these reasons, “rapid data sharing is
p.000043: critical during an unfolding health emergency” (86). It not only constitutes good public health
p.000043: practice but is ethically imperative. Ethically appropriate, rapid shar- ing of data can help in
p.000043: identifying etiological factors; predicting disease spread; evaluating existing and novel treatment,
p.000043: symptomatic care and preventive measures; and guiding
p.000043: the deployment of limited resources. As dis- cussed in the WHO guidance on managing ethical issues in
p.000043: infectious disease outbreaks (49), clinical and research data that are crucial for emergency response should also be
p.000043: shared. Data-sharing is also an obligation under the IHR in both health emergencies and infectious disease
p.000043: outbreaks.
p.000043: As part of continuous pre-epidemic prepared- ness, countries should review their laws, poli- cies and practices on
p.000043: data sharing to ensure that they adequately protect the confiden- tiality of personal information
p.000043: and address other relevant ethical questions, such as set- tling disputes about the ownership or control of
p.000043: surveillance data. Efforts should be made to ensure that rapid sharing of surveillance information with
p.000043: immediate implications for protecting public health and advancing the common good should not preclude
p.000043: subse- quent publication in a scientific journal (87).
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043: Medical student and district surveillance officer investigating suspected Ebola cases in Western Region of
p.000043: Sierra Leone.
p.000043: Source: WHO /Stéphane Saporito
p.000043:
p.000044: 44
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health agencies may use or share surveillance data
p.000044: for research purposes.
p.000044:
p.000044: Surveillance data have often served as a foun- dation for important public health research (88-90). For example,
p.000044: cancer registries have been used in longitudinal epidemiological studies on survival and treatment
...
p.000050: future ethical challenges in pandemic preparedness and response. Monash Bioeth Rev 2015;33:130–147.
p.000050: 29. Lee LM, Thacker SB, St Louis ME, Teutsch SM. Principles and practice of public health surveillance. 3rd Edition.
p.000050: Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2010.
p.000050: 30. Fox RC. Advanced medical technology – social and ethical implications. Annu Rev Sociol
p.000050: 1976;2:231–268.
p.000050: 31. Fox RC, Swazey JP. Medical morality is not bioethics: medical ethics in China and the United States. New
p.000050: Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books; 1988.
p.000050: 32. Rothman JD. Strangers at the bedside: a history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making.
p.000050: New York, NY: Basic Books; 1991.
p.000050: 33. Ackerman HT. Choosing between Nuremberg and the National Commission: balancing of moral principles in clinical
p.000050: research. In: The ethics of research involving human subjects: facing the 21st century. Frederick, MD: University
p.000050: Publishing Group; 1996.
p.000050: 34. International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies. Geneva; Council for Interna- tional
p.000050: Organizations of Medical Sciences; 1991.
p.000050: 35. International ethical guidelines for epidemiological studies. Geneva; Council for International
p.000050: Organizations of Medical Sciences; 2009.
p.000050: 36. Hepple B, Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Public health: ethical issues. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics;
p.000050: 2007.
p.000050: 37. Ethics in epidemics, emergencies and disasters: research, surveillance and patient care: WHO train- ing manual.
p.000050: Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000050: 38. Rubel A. Justifying public health surveillance: basic interests, unreasonable exercise, and privacy. Kennedy
p.000050: Inst Ethics J 2012;22:1–33.
p.000050:
p.000050: References
p.000051: 51
p.000051:
p.000051: 39. Fairchild AL. Dealing with Humpty Dumpty: research, practice, and the ethics of public health
p.000051: surveillance. J Law Med Ethics 2003;31:615–623.
p.000051: 40. Dawson A, Jennings B. The place of solidarity in public health ethics. Public Health Rev 2013;
p.000051: 34:65–79.
p.000051: 41. Beauchamp DE. The health of the republic: epidemics, medicine, and moralism as challenges to democracy.
p.000051: Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press; 1990.
p.000051: 42. Upshur RE. Principles for the justification of public health intervention. Can J Public Health
p.000051: 2002;93:101–103.
p.000051: 43. Kaul I, Faust M. Global public goods and health: taking the agenda forward. Bull World Health
p.000051: Organ 2001;79:869–874.
p.000051: 44. Selgelid MJ. Infectious disease ethics : limiting liberty in contexts of contagion. New York, NY:
p.000051: Springer; 2011.
p.000051: 45. Deneulin S, Townsend N. Public goods, global public goods and the common good. Int J Soc Econ 2007;34:19–36.
p.000051: 46. Closing the gap in a generation: health equity through action on the social determinants of
...
p.000053:
p.000053: 77. Rose G. Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol 1985;14:32–38.
p.000053: 78. Upshur RE, Morin B, Goel V. The privacy paradox: laying Orwell’s ghost to rest. Can Med Assoc J
p.000053: 2001;165:307–309.
p.000053: 79. Davison WL, Kelley RA. ICES report – 2014 prescribed entity review. Toronto, Ontario: Institute for Clinical
p.000053: Evaluative Sciences; 2014.
p.000053: 80. Baggaley R, Johnson C, Garcia Calleja JM, Sabin K, Obermeyer C, Taegtmeyer M, et al. Routine feedback of test
p.000053: results to participants in clinic- and survey-based surveillance of HIV. Bull World Health Organ 2015;93:352–355.
p.000053: 81. Fairchild LA, Ronald. Unlinked anonymous testing for HIV in developing countries: a new ethical consensus.
p.000053: Public Health Rep 2012;127:115–118.
p.000053: 82. Consolidated guidelines on HIV testing services. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000053: 83. Monitoring HIV impact using population-based surveys. Geneva: UNAIDS; 2015.
p.000053: 84. Bernstein AB, Sweeney MH. Public health surveillance data: legal, policy, ethical, regulatory, and practical
p.000053: issues. MMWR Suppl 2012;61:30–34.
p.000053: 85. Klingler C, Silva D, Schuermann C, Reis A, Saxena A, Strech D. Ethical issues in public health sur- veillance: a
p.000053: systematic review. BMC Public Health 2017; 4:17(1): 295
p.000053: 86. Dye C, Bartolomeos K, Moorthy V, Kieny MP. Data sharing in public health emergencies: a call to researchers.
p.000053: Bull World Health Organ 2016;94:158.
p.000053: 87. Langat P, Pisartchik D, Silva D, Bernard C, Olsen K, Smith M, et al. Is there a duty to share? Eth- ics of
p.000053: sharing research data in the context of public health emergencies. Public Health Ethics 2011;4:4–11.
p.000053: 88. Hripcsak G, Bloomrosen M, Flately Brennan P, Chute CG, Cimino J, Detmer DE, et al. Health data use,
p.000053: stewardship, and governance: ongoing gaps and challenges: a report from AMIA’s 2012 health policy meeting. J
p.000053: Am Med Inform Assoc 2014;21:204–211.
p.000053: 89. Geissbuhler A, Safran C, Buchan I, Bellazzi R, Labkoff S, Eilenberg K. Trustworthy reuse of health data: a
p.000053: transnational perspective. Int J Med Inform 2013;82:1–9.
p.000053: 90. Longo LD, Drazen MJ. Data sharing. N Engl J Med 2016;374:276–277.
p.000053: 91. Frakt AB, Bagley N. Protection or harm? Suppressing substance-use data. N Engl J Med
p.000053: 2015;372:1879–1881.
p.000053: 92. Sidel VW, Cohen HW, Gould RM. Good intentions and the road to bioterrorism preparedness. Am J Public Health
p.000053: 2001;91:716–718.
p.000053: 93. Fatima R, Harris RJ, Enarson DA, Hinderaker SG, Qadeer E, Ali K, et al. Estimating tuberculosis
p.000053: burden and case detection in Pakistan. Int J Tuberc Lung Dis 2014;18:55–60.
p.000053: 94. i-IHS. Fighting Ebola using drones. 2014 (http://i-hls.com/archives/40511).
p.000053: 95. Atherton KD. The week in drones: drones fight Ebola, Iranian dogfighters, and more. Keeping up with the droneses.
p.000053: Popular Science, 26 September 2014.
p.000053: 96. Thermal imaging cameras fighting the war on Ebola virus. Las Vegas, NV: Sierra Pacific Innova-
p.000053: tions; 2014 (https://www.x20.org/thermal-imaging-cameras-war-ebola/).
p.000053: 97. Kristin BS. African drone stories. Behemoth J Civilisation 2015;8:73–96.
p.000053:
p.000053:
...
Health / substance use
Searching for indicator substance use:
(return to top)
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
p.000044: research is not appropriate for conducting public health surveillance, surveillance data should be shared only
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
...
Health / visual impairment
Searching for indicator blind:
(return to top)
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
p.000045: preserve trust in public health surveillance systems, there should be compel- ling justification for sharing
p.000045: identifiable data for non-public health uses.
p.000045:
p.000045: Inappropriate sharing of surveillance data is especially controversial in countries in which law enforcement
p.000045: or other agencies have been
p.000045:
...
Searching for indicator blinded:
(return to top)
p.000040: the other, it may lead to injury, stigmatization or discrimination. A decision not to broadly publish data
p.000040: might be justified in exceptional circumstances, when doing so might cause significant harm. Likewise,
p.000040: if the affected population is so small (for example, cases of very rare cancers) that identification of
p.000040: individuals, however inadver- tent, might be inevitable, communication can be limited to preserve privacy (79).
p.000040:
p.000040: Decision-makers must also weigh the harm that could result if affected communities are not informed and
p.000040: thus deprived of knowl- edge and the ability to take action to reduce the risks and the capacity to
p.000040: engage in advo- cacy (see Guideline 13). Those responsible for public health have an affirmative duty to miti- gate
p.000040: the burdens that communication might impose on individuals or groups that are more susceptible to harm or
p.000040: injustice.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is continuing debate about when, if ever, those responsible for the design and conduct of
p.000040: surveillance are ethically obliged to inform the subjects of surveillance about individual results or
p.000040: diagnosis and then refer them to the appropriate service (80). For example, in the early days of the
p.000040: HIV epidemic, when treatment was not avail- able, blinded seroprevalence studies were considered
p.000040: ethically acceptable. In these population-based surveys, HIV status was
p.000040:
p.000040: Guidelines
p.000041: 41
p.000041:
p.000041: not communicated to the study participants. With advances in HIV diagnosis and manage- ment, however, the ethical
p.000041: consensus shifted (81). Guidelines now recommend that sur- veillance systems report results back to con-
p.000041: senting individuals (80, 82, 83). Guidelines also recommend that, after returning results to individuals,
p.000041: those with positive results be referred for proper clinical evaluation, treat- ment and follow-up at
p.000041: nearby health facili- ties. The guidelines also encourage partner testing (76) and referral for
p.000041: psychosocial
p.000041: support. This example underscores the importance of surveillance systems having an engaged
p.000041: oversight body to deal with such issues and make changes on the basis of new evidence or emerging best practices in
p.000041: other jurisdictions (Guideline 2).
p.000041: Relevant ethical considerations in making a judgement about returning information to individuals include
p.000041: feasibility, the possibility of taking action and the potential benefit to the individual.
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
...
Social / Access to Social Goods
Searching for indicator access:
(return to top)
p.000041: obligation to share data with other national and
p.000041: international public health agencies.
p.000043: 43
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties
p.000043: involved in surveillance share data in a timely fashion. 44
p.000043: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health
p.000043: agencies may use or share surveillance data for research purposes. 45
p.000043: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000043: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000046: 46
p.000046: V. The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000048: 48
p.000048: References
p.000050: 50
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000004: 4
p.000004:
p.000004: Foreword
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Public health surveillance is the bedrock of outbreak and epidemic response, but it reaches
p.000004: far beyond infectious diseases. It is sometimes called the radar of public health: it allows health
p.000004: officials to map disease, spot patterns, identify causes, and target interven- tions. Surveillance, for example,
p.000004: is central to understanding the increasing global burden of noncommunicable conditions. By helping to
p.000004: determine patterns and causes of morbidity and mortality, it can help guarantee access to safe food, clean water,
p.000004: pure air, and healthy environments.
p.000004:
p.000004: Surveillance, when conducted ethically, is the foundation for programs to promote human well-being at the
p.000004: population level. It can con- tribute to reducing inequalities: pockets of suf- fering that are unfair, unjust and
p.000004: preventable cannot be addressed if they are not first made visible. But surveillance is not without risks for
p.000004: participants and sometimes poses ethical dilemmas. Issues about privacy, autonomy, equity, and the common
p.000004: good need to be con- sidered and balanced, and knowing how to do so can be challenging in practice.
p.000004:
p.000004: I am pleased to see WHO leading in this impor- tant area by placing ethics at the heart of pub- lic health
p.000004: surveillance. The WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public Health Surveillance is
p.000004: the first international framework of its kind, it fills an important gap. The goal of the guide- line development project
p.000004: was to to help policy- makers and practitioners navigate the ethical issues presented by public health
p.000004: surveillance. This document outlines 17 ethical guidelines that can assist everyone involved in public
p.000004: health surveillance, including officials in gov- ernment agencies, health workers, NGOs and the private sector.
p.000004: I gratefully acknowledge the many experts and WHO colleagues who have made important contributions to
p.000004: this publication.
p.000004:
p.000004: WHO has rightly asserted that public health surveillance, conducted in a manner that anticipates
...
p.000007: Security”, Australia; Wellcome Trust, United Kingdom; and the Institute for Bioethics and Health Policy,
p.000007: University of Miami, USA.
p.000007:
p.000007:
p.000008: 8
p.000008: Acknowledgements
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008: The WHO Strategic Health Operations Centre (SHOC) May 3, 2009.
p.000008: Source: WHO /Christopher Black
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000009: 9
p.000009:
p.000009: I. Introduction
p.000009: Disease surveillance has been a basic public health activity since the late nineteenth century (see Table 1). It
p.000009: is the foundation for initiatives to promote human well-being at the popula- tion level. Public health
p.000009: surveillance is the bed- rock of outbreak and epidemic response, but it reaches far beyond infectious diseases.
p.000009: It can contribute to reducing inequalities: pockets of suffering that are unfair, unjust, and prevent- able
p.000009: cannot be addressed if they are not first made visible (1). It is central to understanding the increasing global
p.000009: burden of noncommuni- cable conditions. By helping to determine pat- terns and causes of morbidity and mortality,
p.000009: public health surveillance can help guarantee
p.000009:
p.000009: access to safe food, clean water, pure air, and healthy environments. Continuous envi- ronmental
p.000009: surveillance may not only identify concerns but also trigger alerts. Occupational disease surveillance can
p.000009: identify workplace exposures and lead to regulation. Surveillance can help create accountable institutions
p.000009: by providing information about health and its determinants. It can provide an evidentiary basis
p.000009: for establishing and evaluating public health policy. Surveillance, for example, will be central to the
p.000009: achievement of the United Nation’s Sustainable Development Goals. The availability of the results of
p.000009: surveillance enables and promotes policy choice. Thus, access to surveillance information can serve as
p.000009: a tool for advocacy when the results are
p.000009:
p.000009: Table 1. Dimensions of public health surveillance
p.000009: Scope
p.000009:
p.000009: Communicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Early detecting and warning of epidemics
p.000009: Noncommunicable diseases
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Trend and spatial analyses
p.000009: Environmental factors
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Risk detection
p.000009: Risk factors and risk markers
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Objectives
p.000009: Generating hypotheses
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Health system
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Monitoring of health system performance
p.000009: Demographic variables
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Evaluation of control measures
p.000009: Health-related events (e.g. food and drug safety, vaccine reactions)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Registries Case reports Repeated
p.000009: surveys
p.000009: Data collection tools
p.000009: Bio-banks Secondary data sources
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Types of analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Population-based (universal or sentinel sites)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Social media
p.000009:
p.000009: Estimation of incidence or prevalence
p.000009: Measurement of associations
p.000009: Assessment of trends
...
p.000015: only infectious diseases and involve not only continuous data collection but may also include focused
p.000015: epidemiological studies; inspection of hazardous conditions or broad oversight of the potential danger posed
p.000015: by food, water or the environment; and screen- ing at workplaces or in health establishments. Table 1 gives an
p.000015: overview of the activities that fall within public health surveillance.
p.000015:
p.000015: While there may be broader and narrower definitions, the understanding of surveillance is that data
p.000015: are collected with the intent of enabling public health action, whether direct intervention,
p.000015: priority-setting, resource alloca- tion or advocacy. “Knowing about the health of a community,” noted one group
p.000015: of surveil- lance specialists, “is the first step to making improvements that support healthy behaviours,
p.000015: identify and address unusual health events, and prevent and treat disease and injury.” (12) In addition to
p.000015: linking surveillance to action to achieve some goal, almost all countries, institu- tions and experts underscore
p.000015: the importance of communicating surveillance results to those “who need to know”, including the public,
p.000015: policy-makers, national and international sci- entific communities, programme planners, public health
p.000015: authorities, medical institutions and funding agencies, to enable intervention, sustainable development or
p.000015: advocacy.
p.000015:
p.000015: The landscape of public health practice is also changing rapidly with regard to the kind of data to which
p.000015: public health agencies have routine access. In some settings, data are recorded by hand and stored on
p.000015: paper; in oth- ers, they are collected, stored and shared via sophisticated electronic systems. The era of
p.000015: “big data,” as discussed in section V, may hold enormous potential for the future of public health surveillance,
p.000015: broadly understood, and has already raised vexing ethical questions.
p.000015:
p.000015: In some jurisdictions, surveillance systems could soon be linked directly to electronic health
p.000015: records. Interoperability between pub- lic health surveillance data sources and clini- cal practice is within
p.000015: reach, in both the public and the private health care sectors (15). Public health data can be used to inform
p.000015: automatic decision-support systems or computational tools to trigger alerts and warnings. Research has shown,
p.000015: further, that geospatial mobile phone data could accurately describe and pre- dict the movement of individuals
p.000015: and thereby the spread of diseases like malaria and H1N1 influenza (16-18).
p.000015:
p.000015: These guidelines define public health surveil- lance systems broadly, building on the general WHO definition of
p.000015: continuous, systematic col- lection, analysis, interpretation, and sharing of health–related data for advocacy and for
p.000015: plan- ning, implementing, and evaluating public health practices. Even if systems are operative, however, new,
p.000015: focused studies are required to respond to epidemiological threats. Further, public health surveillance systems not
p.000015: only rely on but may also inform and improve clinical practice.
p.000015:
p.000015: Surveillance: ethics, law and history
p.000015:
...
p.000027:
p.000027: The Global Health Ethics Unit at WHO created a new mechanism in 2015 to help colleagues working in
p.000027: public health to address ethical issues. Like those of the Ethics Review Board of Public Health Ontario and the Public
p.000027: Health Unit at the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, the mandate of the Public Health Ethics Consultation
p.000027: Service extends beyond surveillance. Programmes and initiatives are not required to be reviewed by this service: WHO
p.000027: staff solicit advice as needed in order to maximize flexibility and ensure that ethical consultation is not viewed as a
p.000027: bureaucratic hurdle. Its advice is informal and non-binding. The group is made up of WHO staff, who receive continuing
p.000027: training in public health ethics and seek advice from the global network of WHO Collaborating Centres for Bioethics.
p.000027: (Source: http://www.who.int/ethics/en/)
p.000027:
p.000027:
p.000028: 28
p.000028: Guidelines
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028: Guideline 3. Surveillance data should be collected only for a legitimate public health purpose.
p.000028:
p.000028: Governments and others involved in public health surveillance should collect only infor- mation that is
p.000028: relevant for legitimate public health purposes, such as to protect, enable or enhance public well-being,
p.000028: reduce morbid- ity and mortality, increase access to the health system and services and reduce health dispari- ties
p.000028: and thereby inequities. All further discus- sions of public health surveillance in these guidelines is
p.000028: based on the assumption that it is undertaken exclusively for a legitimate public health purpose.
p.000028:
p.000028: Literature on good governance usually con- siders legitimate measures to be those that are publicly
p.000028: defensible, morally justified and/
p.000028: or socially acceptable in pursuit of a common good. (53, 54) Any collection of personally identifiable
p.000028: information that does not meet these conditions would be ethically problem- atic. A legitimate public
p.000028: health purpose is required not only for the collection of data but also for the further use of data already
p.000028: in hand.
p.000028:
p.000028: Data collected for clinical purposes (for exam- ple to diagnose infectious disease, to moni- tor microbial
p.000028: resistance, to monitor NCDs like diabetes or to track behaviour associated with coronary heart disease or
p.000028: obesity) can be used for legitimate public health surveillance purposes, provided that such use meets the
p.000028: criteria bar set in guidelines 1, 3, 4 and 7–14 of this document. Such repurposing requires adequate protection of
p.000028: data security and con- fidentiality (Guideline 10).
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028: Children`s Environmental Health in India.
p.000028: Source: WHO /Diego Rodriguez
p.000028:
p.000028: Guidelines
...
p.000030: inevita- bly engage questions of equity and efficiency. As no absolute standard can guide such deter- minations, it is
p.000030: critical that decision-making be transparent, fair and open to revision (58). Governments are accountable for
p.000030: how priori- ties are set. Transparency is important because it fosters trust and creates conditions for citi-
p.000030: zens to advance the common good individually and collectively (59).
p.000030:
p.000030: Transparency is essential with respect to: (i) the aims and duration of any public health surveil- lance activity, (ii)
p.000030: the rationale for such activity relative to explicit health or health care system goals, (iii) the intended benefits
p.000030: and potential burdens to citizens and other actors of public
p.000030: health surveillance, (iv) the scope and methods to be used in collecting data, (v) the intended uses of data and by
p.000030: whom, (vi) the mechanism by which use of data will be monitored, (vii) the mechanism by which subsequent use of
p.000030: data would be overseen at community level and (viii) the recourse that citizens or other actors may have if
p.000030: public health surveillance fails to meet legal and/or ethical standards. Surveillance data should be
p.000030: publicly reported (see Guideline
p.000030: 13) to the extent that they will increase public trust, serve the aim of promoting and protect- ing public health
p.000030: nationally and internation- ally and will not unduly harm any identifiable group or exacerbate inequity (54,
p.000030: 58).
p.000030:
p.000030: Citizens should have access to mechanisms to express their concerns and priorities with regard to
p.000030: surveillance. For example, commu- nities may express concern about a potential cluster of birth defects or
p.000030: cancers that necessi- tates not only targeted epidemiological studies but also the creation of surveillance
p.000030: systems. Priorities should not be set solely by experts nor by those with access to health officials and
p.000030: policy-makers, neglecting populations with less opportunity to voice their concerns.
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030: Pandemic containment exercise (simulation), conducted by the Ministry of Indonesia with the support of WHO Indonesia.
p.000030: Source: WHO / SEARO /Nursila Dewi
p.000030:
p.000030: Guidelines
p.000031: 31
p.000031:
p.000031:
p.000031: Guideline 6. The global community has an obligation to support countries that lack adequate resources to undertake
p.000031: surveillance.
p.000031:
p.000031: Some countries may be unable to establish and maintain public health surveillance of suf- ficient quality, even
p.000031: for high-priority targets that could greatly reduce health inequalities and improve population health,
p.000031: because of severe resource constraints. Equity provides the ethical foundations for claims to interna-
p.000031: tional support. The global community – inter- national health organizations, NGOs, major foundations,
p.000031: countries with a global leader- ship role – has an ethical responsibility to work collaboratively with these
p.000031: countries to support public health surveillance and subsequent interventions. The aim of this requirement
p.000031: of global justice is to reduce health inequalities among countries and improve global health.
p.000031:
p.000031: For example, preventing and limiting the global spread of disease was a key rationale for the
p.000031: obligations under the IHR. Given that outbreaks and risk factors do not recognize borders, the global
...
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
p.000034: however, mitigation strategies can ensure that risks for harm are dealt with adequately. Once harm or
p.000034: potential harm is identified, action must be taken to reduce the risk, or a plan must be in place for
p.000034: reducing, removing or compensating for any harm.
...
p.000034: the common good, they must be free to report without fear of reprisal. As surveillance officials have a
p.000034: responsibility to speak up, they should have protection. This idea is established in the IHR, which
p.000034: protects the confidentiality of those who report a veri- fiable outbreak or a public health event out- side
p.000034: official channels.
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000035: 35
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: Guideline 9. Surveillance of individuals or groups who are particularly susceptible to disease, harm or injustice is
p.000035: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: The HIV oral test on a brothel bed in Belém do Pará, Brazil.
p.000035: Source: Laura Murray
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guideline 10. Governments and others who hold surveillance data must ensure that identifiable data are appropriately
p.000036: secured.
p.000036:
p.000036: Responsible data collection and sharing prac- tices should ensure the security of the data collected in order to
p.000036: respect persons and safe- guard the privacy and other interests of the individuals and communities concerned
p.000036: (50). Every effort must be made to secure records to prevent unauthorized disclosure. Security is
p.000036: different from privacy and confidential- ity, yet it is an essential component of each. “Security” in
p.000036: this context consists of opera- tional and technological safeguards to protect personal data from unauthorized
p.000036: access or disclosure. Maintaining information security is not fool-proof, as electronic databases can be infiltrated.
p.000036:
p.000036: Governments and others who hold surveil- lance data must take appropriate techni- cal and
p.000036: organizational steps to protect data
p.000036: against accidental or unauthorized access, destruction, loss, use or disclosure, whether the data are
p.000036: collected and stored in paper or electronic (digital) format. All personnel with access to public
p.000036: health surveillance data should be trained annually in data security pro- cedures and made aware of their
p.000036: professional ethical responsibility to protect the data and the public. The level of security must be appro-
p.000036: priate to the risks and the nature of the data to be protected, taking into account the state of the art and
p.000036: the cost. In particular, sensitive information, which raises the risks of individu- als and communities for
p.000036: stigmatization or dis- crimination, should be subject to specific and especially rigorous security safeguards.
p.000036:
p.000036: The imperative to secure data should not be considered a license to refuse to use or share surveillance
p.000036: information effectively for legiti- mate public health purposes. (See guidelines 14–17 on sharing and the
p.000036: discussion in Guide- line 2 on meaningful ethics training.)
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Staff at the Medical Records Office sort through patient files at Karapitayam Hospital, Galle.
p.000036: Source: WHO / SEARO /Gary Hampton
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000037: 37
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037: Guideline 11. Under certain circumstances, the collection of names or identifiable data is justified.
p.000037:
p.000037: In some instances, the collection of names or identifiable data is both technically and ethically
...
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041: Map of parasitic disease epidemic area in China at the National Institute of Parasitic Diseases in
p.000041: Shanghai, China. 16 May 2010.
p.000041: Source: WHO / TDR /Simon Lim
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000042: 42
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guideline 14. With appropriate safeguards and justification, those responsible
p.000042: for public health surveillance have an obligation to share data with other national and international public health
p.000042: agencies.
p.000042:
p.000042: For a public health surveillance system to be effective, equitable, and promote the com- mon good, it must
p.000042: be capable of receiving and linking data from public agencies responsible for public health. For example, because
p.000042: of the stringent data security that has surrounded HIV surveillance, there have been situations in which data on
p.000042: HIV status have not been shared with those responsible for tuberculosis surveil- lance, obviating systematic
p.000042: identification of cases with co-infection. Public health work- ers cannot respond appropriately to swiftly
p.000042: changing infectious diseases in real time or take appropriate action in the case of chronic conditions without
p.000042: access to appropriate data. The same is true of occupational exposures. There have been examples in which
p.000042: agencies responsible for tracking occupational diseases have not shared data (despite the absence of a
p.000042: prohibition) with agencies responsible for
p.000042: worker protection and workplace regulation (23). A review of the literature indicated that much of the
p.000042: failure to share information is due to poor planning rather than safety concerns. Programmes have experienced
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
p.000042: re-shared by other agencies, except under the conditions specified elsewhere in this document, e.g. in
p.000042: guidelines 16–17. When the protection of different datasets is not equivalent, the more stringent
p.000042: privacy standard should be applied.
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
...
p.000043: and address other relevant ethical questions, such as set- tling disputes about the ownership or control of
p.000043: surveillance data. Efforts should be made to ensure that rapid sharing of surveillance information with
p.000043: immediate implications for protecting public health and advancing the common good should not preclude
p.000043: subse- quent publication in a scientific journal (87).
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043: Medical student and district surveillance officer investigating suspected Ebola cases in Western Region of
p.000043: Sierra Leone.
p.000043: Source: WHO /Stéphane Saporito
p.000043:
p.000044: 44
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health agencies may use or share surveillance data
p.000044: for research purposes.
p.000044:
p.000044: Surveillance data have often served as a foun- dation for important public health research (88-90). For example,
p.000044: cancer registries have been used in longitudinal epidemiological studies on survival and treatment
p.000044: efficacy. It may be permissible to share surveillance data with researchers undertaking studies that (i) are
p.000044: sufficiently important for advancement of the common good and (ii) would not be feasible without access
p.000044: to the surveillance data in question. There may sometimes be disagreement about what should be con-
p.000044: sidered “sufficiently important” research to justify sharing of surveillance data for research
p.000044: purposes. This is a matter that local governments, public health authorities and/ or research ethics committees
p.000044: (as described below) should judge, taking into account the considerations and guidelines set out in this
p.000044: document.
p.000044:
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
p.000044: research is not appropriate for conducting public health surveillance, surveillance data should be shared only
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
p.000045: preserve trust in public health surveillance systems, there should be compel- ling justification for sharing
p.000045: identifiable data for non-public health uses.
p.000045:
p.000045: Inappropriate sharing of surveillance data is especially controversial in countries in which law enforcement
p.000045: or other agencies have been
p.000045:
p.000045: implicated in systematic violations of human rights. In these contexts, collaboration with law enforcement
p.000045: agencies may undermine trust in public health surveillance, creating a disincentive for seeking care or
p.000045: honest report- ing of data. This is a particular concern for individuals or groups in situations of particular
p.000045: vulnerability (92). Further, such unwarranted sharing will potentially inflict long-term dam- age on public
p.000045: health efforts more broadly.
p.000045:
p.000045: The governance mechanisms recommended in Guideline 2 should ensure that the exceptional conditions, if any, under which
p.000045: identifiable sur- veillance data may be shared are specified and made transparent. Such a review will require
p.000045: determination of whether the threat is of suf- ficient magnitude to warrant potential damage to the integrity of and
p.000045: trust in public health sur- veillance systems. Sanctions must be in place to prevent inappropriate data-sharing
p.000045: by public health agencies and inappropriate use of data by agencies outside the public health sector.
p.000045:
p.000045:
...
Social / Age
Searching for indicator age:
(return to top)
p.000042: for public health surveillance have an obligation to share data with other national and international public health
p.000042: agencies.
p.000042:
p.000042: For a public health surveillance system to be effective, equitable, and promote the com- mon good, it must
p.000042: be capable of receiving and linking data from public agencies responsible for public health. For example, because
p.000042: of the stringent data security that has surrounded HIV surveillance, there have been situations in which data on
p.000042: HIV status have not been shared with those responsible for tuberculosis surveil- lance, obviating systematic
p.000042: identification of cases with co-infection. Public health work- ers cannot respond appropriately to swiftly
p.000042: changing infectious diseases in real time or take appropriate action in the case of chronic conditions without
p.000042: access to appropriate data. The same is true of occupational exposures. There have been examples in which
p.000042: agencies responsible for tracking occupational diseases have not shared data (despite the absence of a
p.000042: prohibition) with agencies responsible for
p.000042: worker protection and workplace regulation (23). A review of the literature indicated that much of the
p.000042: failure to share information is due to poor planning rather than safety concerns. Programmes have experienced
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
p.000042: re-shared by other agencies, except under the conditions specified elsewhere in this document, e.g. in
p.000042: guidelines 16–17. When the protection of different datasets is not equivalent, the more stringent
p.000042: privacy standard should be applied.
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000043: 43
p.000043:
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties involved in surveillance share data
p.000043: in a timely fashion.
p.000043: The collection and sharing of data are essen- tial activities in ordinary public health practice. During
p.000043: emergencies, data-sharing takes on increased importance because of the urgency of the situation,
...
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000045: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000045:
p.000045: While aggregate public health data may be widely shared with agencies outside the health sector
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
p.000045: preserve trust in public health surveillance systems, there should be compel- ling justification for sharing
p.000045: identifiable data for non-public health uses.
p.000045:
p.000045: Inappropriate sharing of surveillance data is especially controversial in countries in which law enforcement
p.000045: or other agencies have been
p.000045:
p.000045: implicated in systematic violations of human rights. In these contexts, collaboration with law enforcement
p.000045: agencies may undermine trust in public health surveillance, creating a disincentive for seeking care or
p.000045: honest report- ing of data. This is a particular concern for individuals or groups in situations of particular
p.000045: vulnerability (92). Further, such unwarranted sharing will potentially inflict long-term dam- age on public
p.000045: health efforts more broadly.
p.000045:
p.000045: The governance mechanisms recommended in Guideline 2 should ensure that the exceptional conditions, if any, under which
p.000045: identifiable sur- veillance data may be shared are specified and made transparent. Such a review will require
p.000045: determination of whether the threat is of suf- ficient magnitude to warrant potential damage to the integrity of and
p.000045: trust in public health sur- veillance systems. Sanctions must be in place to prevent inappropriate data-sharing
p.000045: by public health agencies and inappropriate use of data by agencies outside the public health sector.
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: WHO Immunization officers visit Quang Binh Province, Viet Nam to monitor the Measles-Rubella Immunization campaign.
p.000045: Source: WHO / WPRO /Emmanuel Eraly
p.000045:
p.000046: 46
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046: A barcode is placed at the entrance of houses. After being flashed with a smartphone, the barcode provides information
p.000046: about whether the house was controlled and declared dengue free or not.
p.000046: Source: WHO/TDR /Catalina Cardenas
p.000046:
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000047: 47
p.000047:
...
p.000051: 46. Closing the gap in a generation: health equity through action on the social determinants of
p.000051: health: final report of the commission on social determinants of health. Geneva: World Health Organization;
p.002008: 2008
p.002008: 47. Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis prevention, care and control. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2010.
p.002008: 48. Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB strategy. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2017.
p.002008: 49. Guidance for managing ethical issues in infectious disease outbreaks. Geneva: World Health Orga- nization; 2016.
p.002008: 50. Scott JC. Seeing like a state: how certain schemes to improve the human condition have failed. New Haven, CT:
p.002008: Yale University Press; 1998.
p.002008: 51. Promoting the health of refugees and migrants. Executive Board resolution 140/24. Geneva: World
p.002008: Health Organization; 2017.
p.002008: 52. Willison DJ, Ondrusek N, Dawson A, Emerson C, Ferris LE, Saginur R, et al. What makes public
p.002008: health studies ethical? Dissolving the boundary between research and practice. BMC Med Ethics 2014;15:61.
p.002008: 53. Graham J, Amos B, Plumptre T. Principles for Good Governance in the 21st Century: Policy Brief
p.002008: No. 15. Ottawa: Institute on Governance, 1993. Available at: http://iog.ca/wp-content/
p.002008: uploads/2012/12/2003_August_policybrief151.pdf
p.002008: 54. United Nations Development Programme. Chapter 8: Governance Principles, Institutional Capac- ity, and Quality.
p.002008: In Towards human resilience: sustaining MDG progress in an age of economic uncertainty. New York: United
p.002008: Nations Development Programme, 2011. Available at: http://www.
p.002008: undp.org/content/undp/en/home/librarypage/poverty-reduction/inclusive_development/towards_
p.002008: human_resiliencesustainingmdgprogressinanageofeconomicun.html54.
p.002008: 55. Expert information. Tokyo: Japan Ministry of Health, Labour and Welfare (http://www.mhlw.go.jp/
p.002008: bunya/kenkou/kekkaku-kansenshou11/dl/01_kansensho.pdf).
p.002008:
p.002008:
p.000052: 52
p.000052: References
p.000052:
p.000052: 56. German RR, Lee LM, Horan JM, Milstein RL, Pertowski CA, Waller MN, et al. Updated guidelines for evaluating
p.000052: public health surveillance systems: recommendations from the Guidelines Working Group. MMWR Recomm Rep 2001;50:1-35;
p.000052: quiz CE1-7.
p.000052: 57. Brock DW, Wikler D. Ethical challenges in long-term funding for HIV/AIDS. Health Aff (Millwood)
p.000052: 2009;28:1666–1676.
p.000052: 58. Daniels N. Accountability for reasonableness: establishing a fair process for priority setting is easier than
p.000052: agreeing on principles. BMJ 2000;321:1300–1301.
p.000052: 59. O’Neill O. Trust, trustworthiness and transparency. Brussels: European Foundation Centre; 2015.
p.000052: 60. WHO framework convention on tobacco control. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2003.
p.000052: 61. United Nations framework convention on climate change. New York, NY: United Nations; 2015.
p.000052: 62. Calain P. From the field side of the binoculars: a different view on global public health surveillance. Health
p.000052: Policy Plan 2007;22:13–20.
...
Social / Child
Searching for indicator children:
(return to top)
p.000020: broadly conceived than in the narrow economic sense.
p.000020: Equity: Public health ethics is centrally concerned with the idea of equity. It is well established that
p.000020: social inequality has adverse effects on health (46). Not all inequality is within human control or is
p.000020: morally relevant. Morally prob- lematic inequality is commonly referred to as inequity. A just or fair society
p.000020: will attempt to provide equitable conditions for humans to flourish, with health as a central component.
p.000020: Equity some- times requires that the most vulnerable people receive what may appear to be disproportionate
p.000020: resources: that is, the unfair distribution of risks requires addi- tional resources to balance the scales.
p.000020: Public health surveillance can further the pursuit of equity by identifying the particular problems
p.000020: of disadvantaged populations, including global communi- ties, providing the evidence for focused health campaigns
p.000020: and identifying the basis of unfair differences in health.
p.000020:
p.000020: Respect for persons: Public health eth- ics is concerned with the rights, liberty, and other interests of individuals
p.000020: as well as overall population well-being. When- ever possible, individuals should be involved in decisions
p.000020: that affect them. In some cases, individuals should be free to make their own choices; in other cases,
p.000020: when population-level interven- tions may be necessary, individuals can be consulted and involved in
p.000020: decision- making. But many individuals (such as young children) cannot make their own choices, and the State has
p.000020: an obligation to protect them and promote their long- term health interests. Undertaking pub- lic health surveillance
p.000020: is, itself, arguably an expression of respect for persons. This further requires ensuring that data about
p.000020: individuals and groups are pro- tected and risks for harm are minimized
p.000020:
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000021: 21
p.000021:
p.000021:
p.000021: to the greatest possible extent. Finally, surveillance further engenders respect for persons by making
p.000021: protection or amelioration possible.
p.000021:
p.000021: Good governance: Although good gov- ernance is not an ethical principle but rather a political aspiration, it
p.000021: is subject to a number of ethical considerations. To ensure that the ethical challenges posed by public health
p.000021: action are addressed systematically and fairly, governance mechanisms must be accountable and open to
p.000021: public scrutiny. Although pro- tection of the common good must draw on the best available evidence,
p.000021: decisions will have to be made in the face of uncertainty. Accountability, transparency and community
p.000021: engage- ment are means of justifying public policy structures that promote respect for persons,
p.000021: equity, and the common good. Transparency requires that poli- cies and procedures for surveillance be
...
p.000024:
p.000024: Public health surveillance activities require investment of societal resources to preserve, protect and
p.000024: promote health. In all countries, but especially in low-resource settings, allo- cating societal resources for
p.000024: public health sur- veillance requires prioritization. This issue is discussed further in Guideline 5.
p.000024:
p.000024: Guidelines
p.000025: 25
p.000025:
p.000025: Once surveillance data are available, Member States have the moral duty to use the data actively to promote
p.000025: better health outcomes. Even when resources limit the capacity of countries to take immediate action
p.000025: on the basis of the findings of public health surveil- lance, the data provide the evidentiary basis for
p.000025: advocacy directed at both the national
p.000025: and global communities, thus potentially empowering the most vulnerable. The pur- suit of equity
p.000025: establishes a warrant for sur- veillance, and the global community should provide the necessary help in
p.000025: moving from collecting and analysing data to action (see Guideline 6).
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
p.000026: include: collecting data elements that reveal stigmatized behaviour; adding new elements of data collection, such
p.000026: as measurements of CD4 counts as part of routine HIV/AIDS surveillance; adopting new uses for existing
p.000026: surveillance data, such as for case management or contact tracing; or using public health surveillance data for
p.000026: commercial or security purposes.
p.000026:
p.000026: In the case of research, review committees monitor adherence to ethics standards. Such an independent,
...
p.000028: reduce morbid- ity and mortality, increase access to the health system and services and reduce health dispari- ties
p.000028: and thereby inequities. All further discus- sions of public health surveillance in these guidelines is
p.000028: based on the assumption that it is undertaken exclusively for a legitimate public health purpose.
p.000028:
p.000028: Literature on good governance usually con- siders legitimate measures to be those that are publicly
p.000028: defensible, morally justified and/
p.000028: or socially acceptable in pursuit of a common good. (53, 54) Any collection of personally identifiable
p.000028: information that does not meet these conditions would be ethically problem- atic. A legitimate public
p.000028: health purpose is required not only for the collection of data but also for the further use of data already
p.000028: in hand.
p.000028:
p.000028: Data collected for clinical purposes (for exam- ple to diagnose infectious disease, to moni- tor microbial
p.000028: resistance, to monitor NCDs like diabetes or to track behaviour associated with coronary heart disease or
p.000028: obesity) can be used for legitimate public health surveillance purposes, provided that such use meets the
p.000028: criteria bar set in guidelines 1, 3, 4 and 7–14 of this document. Such repurposing requires adequate protection of
p.000028: data security and con- fidentiality (Guideline 10).
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028:
p.000028: Children`s Environmental Health in India.
p.000028: Source: WHO /Diego Rodriguez
p.000028:
p.000028: Guidelines
p.000029: 29
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029: Guideline 4. Countries have an obligation to ensure that the data collected are of sufficient quality, including being
p.000029: timely, reliable and valid, to achieve public health goals.
p.000029:
p.000029: Data should meet the most exacting yet reasonable standards with regard to com- pleteness,
p.000029: uniqueness, timeliness, validity, accuracy and consistency for the purpose and the resources available to
p.000029: fulfil that purpose. Where relevant, this requirement extends to external quality assurance of laboratory
p.000029: data. The quality of data is a precondition of their ethical use. Determining the adequacy of data,
p.000029: however, depends, in part, on whether they are to be used to intervene at the level of the individual
p.000029: (e.g. contact tracing) or the population (e.g. estimating the incidence and prevalence of a
p.000029: disease or exposure). Their adequacy will also depend on whether a disease is infectious, noncommunicable
p.000029: or environmental, and whether the condition is chronic or acute. How data quality is assured from a
p.000029: technical perspective will depend on the priority, the context and the type of sur- veillance. While some
p.000029: countries and institu- tions explicitly stress the accuracy or reliability of data (55), others value rapid
p.000029: collection of useful data over complete accuracy.
p.000029:
p.000029: Countries have obligations to ensure suf- ficient numbers of trained staff to generate and competently
p.000029: analyse surveillance data
p.000029:
...
Social / Incarcerated
Searching for indicator liberty:
(return to top)
p.000020: surveillance are at risk. There is a complex literature on economics and moral philosophy that seeks to define and
p.000020: distinguish the terms “public good”, “public goods,” and “the com- mon good” (45). After careful delibera-
p.000020: tion, the committee adopted the term “the common good” to capture the notion of public goods more
p.000020: broadly conceived than in the narrow economic sense.
p.000020: Equity: Public health ethics is centrally concerned with the idea of equity. It is well established that
p.000020: social inequality has adverse effects on health (46). Not all inequality is within human control or is
p.000020: morally relevant. Morally prob- lematic inequality is commonly referred to as inequity. A just or fair society
p.000020: will attempt to provide equitable conditions for humans to flourish, with health as a central component.
p.000020: Equity some- times requires that the most vulnerable people receive what may appear to be disproportionate
p.000020: resources: that is, the unfair distribution of risks requires addi- tional resources to balance the scales.
p.000020: Public health surveillance can further the pursuit of equity by identifying the particular problems
p.000020: of disadvantaged populations, including global communi- ties, providing the evidence for focused health campaigns
p.000020: and identifying the basis of unfair differences in health.
p.000020:
p.000020: Respect for persons: Public health eth- ics is concerned with the rights, liberty, and other interests of individuals
p.000020: as well as overall population well-being. When- ever possible, individuals should be involved in decisions
p.000020: that affect them. In some cases, individuals should be free to make their own choices; in other cases,
p.000020: when population-level interven- tions may be necessary, individuals can be consulted and involved in
p.000020: decision- making. But many individuals (such as young children) cannot make their own choices, and the State has
p.000020: an obligation to protect them and promote their long- term health interests. Undertaking pub- lic health surveillance
p.000020: is, itself, arguably an expression of respect for persons. This further requires ensuring that data about
p.000020: individuals and groups are pro- tected and risks for harm are minimized
p.000020:
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000021: 21
p.000021:
p.000021:
p.000021: to the greatest possible extent. Finally, surveillance further engenders respect for persons by making
p.000021: protection or amelioration possible.
p.000021:
p.000021: Good governance: Although good gov- ernance is not an ethical principle but rather a political aspiration, it
p.000021: is subject to a number of ethical considerations. To ensure that the ethical challenges posed by public health
p.000021: action are addressed systematically and fairly, governance mechanisms must be accountable and open to
...
p.000050: Organizations of Medical Sciences; 2009.
p.000050: 36. Hepple B, Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Public health: ethical issues. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics;
p.000050: 2007.
p.000050: 37. Ethics in epidemics, emergencies and disasters: research, surveillance and patient care: WHO train- ing manual.
p.000050: Geneva: World Health Organization; 2015.
p.000050: 38. Rubel A. Justifying public health surveillance: basic interests, unreasonable exercise, and privacy. Kennedy
p.000050: Inst Ethics J 2012;22:1–33.
p.000050:
p.000050: References
p.000051: 51
p.000051:
p.000051: 39. Fairchild AL. Dealing with Humpty Dumpty: research, practice, and the ethics of public health
p.000051: surveillance. J Law Med Ethics 2003;31:615–623.
p.000051: 40. Dawson A, Jennings B. The place of solidarity in public health ethics. Public Health Rev 2013;
p.000051: 34:65–79.
p.000051: 41. Beauchamp DE. The health of the republic: epidemics, medicine, and moralism as challenges to democracy.
p.000051: Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press; 1990.
p.000051: 42. Upshur RE. Principles for the justification of public health intervention. Can J Public Health
p.000051: 2002;93:101–103.
p.000051: 43. Kaul I, Faust M. Global public goods and health: taking the agenda forward. Bull World Health
p.000051: Organ 2001;79:869–874.
p.000051: 44. Selgelid MJ. Infectious disease ethics : limiting liberty in contexts of contagion. New York, NY:
p.000051: Springer; 2011.
p.000051: 45. Deneulin S, Townsend N. Public goods, global public goods and the common good. Int J Soc Econ 2007;34:19–36.
p.000051: 46. Closing the gap in a generation: health equity through action on the social determinants of
p.000051: health: final report of the commission on social determinants of health. Geneva: World Health Organization;
p.002008: 2008
p.002008: 47. Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis prevention, care and control. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2010.
p.002008: 48. Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB strategy. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2017.
p.002008: 49. Guidance for managing ethical issues in infectious disease outbreaks. Geneva: World Health Orga- nization; 2016.
p.002008: 50. Scott JC. Seeing like a state: how certain schemes to improve the human condition have failed. New Haven, CT:
p.002008: Yale University Press; 1998.
p.002008: 51. Promoting the health of refugees and migrants. Executive Board resolution 140/24. Geneva: World
p.002008: Health Organization; 2017.
p.002008: 52. Willison DJ, Ondrusek N, Dawson A, Emerson C, Ferris LE, Saginur R, et al. What makes public
p.002008: health studies ethical? Dissolving the boundary between research and practice. BMC Med Ethics 2014;15:61.
p.002008: 53. Graham J, Amos B, Plumptre T. Principles for Good Governance in the 21st Century: Policy Brief
p.002008: No. 15. Ottawa: Institute on Governance, 1993. Available at: http://iog.ca/wp-content/
p.002008: uploads/2012/12/2003_August_policybrief151.pdf
...
Social / Linguistic Proficiency
Searching for indicator language:
(return to top)
p.000019: appropriate ethical guidance and review – that is, for a para- digm of accountability that responds to
p.000019: the demands of public health and that is distinct from the systems that have governed research for half a
p.000019: century.
p.000019:
p.000019: Public health ethics
p.000019:
p.000019: The discipline of public health ethics has developed rapidly during the past two decades.
p.000019: Its central focus has been on articu- lating and exploring the ethical issues that arise in the pursuit of
p.000019: population health. This has resulted in a focus on concepts such as the common good, equity,
p.000019: solidarity, reci- procity, and population well-being. This is not to say that more individual values
p.000019: such as autonomy, privacy, and individual rights
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019: A crowd at a community event to launch a vaccination campaign.
p.000019: Source: WHO /Garry Smyth
p.000019:
p.000020: 20
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020: and liberties are not also important ethical considerations; however, these more “social” or “public” values are
p.000020: reflected in related yet not wholly overlapping concepts that capture the broad importance of community and the
p.000020: affirmative duty to act. Some in the field use the language of solidarity (40), drawing on the communitarian
p.000020: tradition in public health (41); others describe the mutual obligations of reciprocity (42). The Nuffield
p.000020: Council on Bioethics sought to capture the duties and responsibilities of government in relation to public
p.000020: health by the concept of “steward- ship” (36).
p.000020:
p.000020: After a careful review, reflection and delibera- tion, the WHO Guidelines Development Group determined that the
p.000020: following ethical consid- erations are of particular importance for public health surveillance. They represent
p.000020: the back- bone of the guidelines:
p.000020:
p.000020: Common good: Surveillance is widely acknowledged to be a public good (43), and some of the benefits
p.000020: it pro- vides cannot be subdivided into indi- vidual private benefits because they are fundamentally shared (41,
p.000020: 44). Surveil- lance is justified, fundamentally, as a requirement for the good of all. With- out adequate
p.000020: oversight by public health bodies and the participation of individ- uals and communities, the shared ben- efits of
p.000020: surveillance are at risk. There is a complex literature on economics and moral philosophy that seeks to define and
p.000020: distinguish the terms “public good”, “public goods,” and “the com- mon good” (45). After careful delibera-
p.000020: tion, the committee adopted the term “the common good” to capture the notion of public goods more
p.000020: broadly conceived than in the narrow economic sense.
p.000020: Equity: Public health ethics is centrally concerned with the idea of equity. It is well established that
...
p.000021: public scrutiny. Although pro- tection of the common good must draw on the best available evidence,
p.000021: decisions will have to be made in the face of uncertainty. Accountability, transparency and community
p.000021: engage- ment are means of justifying public policy structures that promote respect for persons,
p.000021: equity, and the common good. Transparency requires that poli- cies and procedures for surveillance be
p.000021: communicated clearly and that affected individuals or communities be aware of any decisions concerning them. Trans-
p.000021: parency also requires public reporting of the results of surveillance (in ano- nymized or aggregated form).
p.000021: Without such knowledge, communities cannot be empowered to demand government action or to protect themselves in
p.000021: the absence of alternatives.
p.000021:
p.000021: These are not the only relevant ethical consid- erations with regard to the nature of surveil- lance programmes
p.000021: and practice but the ones considered central to making decisions in the specific context of public health
p.000021: surveillance by those involved in development of these guidelines.
p.000021:
p.000021: While over the past few decades the global discourse on research ethics has come to
p.000021:
p.000021: an agreement on how best to frame issues, public health ethics has not reached such a juncture. Thus,
p.000021: even in documents explicitly grounded in public health ethics, differences in language and emphasis remain.
p.000021: This docu- ment is one of three recent WHO-sponsored initiatives to develop ethical frameworks for
p.000021: disease control. Building on the original “Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis preven- tion, care and
p.000021: control” in 2010 (47), the “Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB Strategy” (48) addresses
p.000021: the most critical challenges to reducing the number of deaths from tuberculosis by 95% by 2030
p.000021: and the number of new cases by 90% between 2015 and 2035. The “Guidance for managing ethical issues in
p.000021: infectious disease outbreaks” (49) in 2016, in response to the outbreak of Ebola virus disease in West Africa
p.000021: in 2014–2015, underscored the importance of providing ethics guidance beyond “a spe- cific pathogen in
p.000021: isolation” to “cross-cutting ethical issues that apply to infectious disease outbreaks generally”.
p.000021:
p.000021: The three projects obviously have important continuity. All, for example, emphasize equity, justice, and the
p.000021: common good (sometimes expressed as “stewardship” or “reciproc- ity”). All stress the importance
p.000021: of respecting the dignity of persons (sometimes emphasiz- ing autonomy or privacy). Accountability and the
p.000021: importance of good governance either explicitly or implicitly informs all three. They also have
p.000021: relevant differences that reflect the subject of each. The tuberculosis guidelines, for example, address the
...
p.000044: sufficiently important for advancement of the common good and (ii) would not be feasible without access
p.000044: to the surveillance data in question. There may sometimes be disagreement about what should be con-
p.000044: sidered “sufficiently important” research to justify sharing of surveillance data for research
p.000044: purposes. This is a matter that local governments, public health authorities and/ or research ethics committees
p.000044: (as described below) should judge, taking into account the considerations and guidelines set out in this
p.000044: document.
p.000044:
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
p.000044: research is not appropriate for conducting public health surveillance, surveillance data should be shared only
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
...
Social / Marital Status
Searching for indicator single:
(return to top)
p.000012: transparently. Countries should ensure implementation of these guidelines and monitor it regularly.
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012:
p.000012: Introduction
p.000013: 13
p.000013:
p.000013: II. Background
p.000013: Defining public health surveillance
p.000013:
p.000013: Some countries define surveillance narrowly, others quite broadly. These guidelines cover surveillance as
p.000013: broadly understood. In the simplest formulations, surveillance is defined as “continued watchfulness” (6) or
p.000013: “the mon- itoring of events in humans, linked to action” (7). WHO generally defines surveillance as “the continuous,
p.000013: systematic collection, analysis and interpretation of health-related data needed for the planning,
p.000013: implementation, and evalu- ation of public health practice” (8). Health data are those pertaining to
p.000013: communicable and NCDs, injuries and conditions and their related risks and determinants. For infectious
p.000013: disease outbreaks (and events that suggest a “potential for international disease spread”), the
p.000013: International Health Regulations (2005) (IHR) define surveillance as “the systematic on-going
p.000013: collection, collation and analysis of data for public health purposes and the timely dissemination of public
p.000013: health information for assessment and public health response as necessary” (9).
p.000013: Understanding of public health surveillance differs considerably from country to country. Although surveillance is
p.000013: usually described as systematic or continuous, not all countries, institutions or scholars single out the
p.000013: rou- tine nature of public health surveillance but rather emphasize the purpose and function of data
p.000013: collection (see Table 1). Likewise, although disease and injury always figure centrally, some
p.000013: definitions include determi- nants of important public health events (10) and environmental conditions that
p.000013: affect health (11). Vital registration of events like births and deaths, although often not specif- ically
p.000013: described as part of a “public health” surveillance system, is often considered to be surveillance.
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013: Health worker collecting records and filling out surveys with the inhabitants of Salto, Uruguay.
p.000013: Source: WHO/TDR /Sebastian Oliel
p.000013:
p.000013:
p.000013: Although international agencies often spon- sor, subsidize and oversee national surveys in low- and
p.000013: middle-income countries to track trends in risk factors or health outcomes, national public health
p.000013: authorities are usu- ally responsible for public health surveillance systems and activities. The IHR,
p.000013: however, recognizes surveillance data from beyond the formal channels of reporting, including unof- ficial
p.000013: or informal sources, provided that they meet standards of reliability and validity.
p.000013:
p.000013: For some organizations and experts, only those activities in which the purpose of data gather- ing has been defined in
p.000013: advance and, indeed, in which the questions driving data collec- tion are set in advance meet the definition of
...
Social / Presence of Coercion
Searching for indicator coerced:
(return to top)
p.000017: between showing “good” results or losing their jobs, adversely affecting the quality of data in some settings (26, 27).
p.000017:
p.000017: These guidelines are based on the understand- ing that surveillance is so fundamental a public health practice that
p.000017: its advancement cannot depend on crises or citizen protests to make the case for tracking disease for
p.000017: the sake of public health. While these guidelines represent a call to action, it is not a call to unrestrained
p.000017: action. Rather, public health surveillance, con- ducted in a manner that anticipates ethical challenges and
p.000017: proactively seeks to reduce unnecessary risks, provides the architecture for social well-being.
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000018: 18
p.000018: Background
p.000018:
p.000018: III. Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000018:
p.000018: Existing guidelines
p.000018:
p.000018: Limited academic literature on the practice of public health surveillance addresses the major ethical questions that
p.000018: arise in data collection; when the data are actually stored, used and shared; and data dissemination. The
p.000018: academic literature is (28), however, no substitute for guidelines that go beyond current disease-
p.000018: specific, national recommendations (29).
p.000018:
p.000018: In the decades since the Second World War, both international and national bodies have proposed ethical
p.000018: principles, guidelines and laws to govern research with human sub- jects. In response to egregious
p.000018: harm inflicted on individuals coerced into clinical research, new codes of ethics uniformly prioritized indi-
p.000018: vidual self-determination and emphasized the importance of informed consent for research, while acknowledging that
p.000018: it would hardly be straightforward in complex situations to bal- ance the protection of human research
p.000018: sub- jects against the social benefit of the research. In the practice of clinical ethics, autonomy assumed a
p.000018: place of singular importance, rep- resenting a fundamental change in a moral world view (30-33).
p.000018:
p.000018: In its “International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies” in 1991, CIOMS acknowledged that
p.000018: existing guidance focused on “patients and individual subjects” was not sufficient for studies involving
p.000018: “groups” of people. After considerable controversy, a con- sensus emerged: CIOMS stressed the impor- tance of
p.000018: the principles of research ethics first set out in the Nuremberg Code but recognized that application in the
p.000018: epidemiological context would require flexibility (34). The tradition that developed was one in
p.000018: which research
p.000018:
...
Social / Property Ownership
Searching for indicator home:
(return to top)
p.000024: promote health. In all countries, but especially in low-resource settings, allo- cating societal resources for
p.000024: public health sur- veillance requires prioritization. This issue is discussed further in Guideline 5.
p.000024:
p.000024: Guidelines
p.000025: 25
p.000025:
p.000025: Once surveillance data are available, Member States have the moral duty to use the data actively to promote
p.000025: better health outcomes. Even when resources limit the capacity of countries to take immediate action
p.000025: on the basis of the findings of public health surveil- lance, the data provide the evidentiary basis for
p.000025: advocacy directed at both the national
p.000025: and global communities, thus potentially empowering the most vulnerable. The pur- suit of equity
p.000025: establishes a warrant for sur- veillance, and the global community should provide the necessary help in
p.000025: moving from collecting and analysing data to action (see Guideline 6).
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
p.000026: include: collecting data elements that reveal stigmatized behaviour; adding new elements of data collection, such
p.000026: as measurements of CD4 counts as part of routine HIV/AIDS surveillance; adopting new uses for existing
p.000026: surveillance data, such as for case management or contact tracing; or using public health surveillance data for
p.000026: commercial or security purposes.
p.000026:
p.000026: In the case of research, review committees monitor adherence to ethics standards. Such an independent,
p.000026: impartial oversight mecha- nism allows for close scrutiny and can ensure that relevant protection is
...
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048:
p.000048: Sphere and continents with binary code zero – one.
p.000048: Source: CC0 Public Domain
p.000048:
p.000048: The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000049: 49
p.000049:
p.000049: References
p.000049:
p.000049: 1. Sustainable Development Goals. New York, NY: United Nations; 2015 (http://www.un.org/
p.000049: sustainabledevelopment/sustainable-development-goals/, accessed 19 December 2016).
p.000049: 2. Fairchild AL, Bayer R, Colgrove JK, Wolfe D. Searching eyes. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press;
p.000049: 2007.
p.000049: 3. Calain P, Sa’Da CA. Coincident polio and Ebola crises expose similar fault lines in the current global health
p.000049: regime. Conflict Health 2015;9:29.
p.000049: 4. Selgelid MJ. Bioethics. New York, NY: Macmillan; 2014.
p.000049: 5. WHO handbook for guideline development. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2014.
p.000049: 6. Declich S, Carter AO. Public health surveillance: historical origins, methods and evaluation. Bull
p.000049: World Health Organ 1994;72:285–304.
p.000049: 7. Institute of Medicine. Addressing foodborne threats to health: policies, practices, and global coor- dination.
p.000049: Workshop summary. Washington DC: National Academies Press; 2006.
p.000049: 8. WHO health topics | Public health surveillance. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2014
p.000049: (http://www.who.int/topics/public_health_surveillance/en/, accessed 19 December 2016).
p.000049: 9. International health regulations. 3rd Edition. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2005.
p.000049: 10. Area surveillance. Buenos Aires: Ministry of Health; 2017 (http://www.msal.gob.ar/index.php/
p.000049: home/funciones/area-de-vigilancia).
p.000049: 11. O’Carroll PW. Public health informatics and information systems. New York, NY: Springer; 2003.
p.000049: 12. Lee LM, Thacker SB. Public health surveillance and knowing about health in the context of grow- ing sources of
p.000049: health data. Am J Prev Med 2011;41:636–640.
p.000049: 13. Surveillance systems reported in Communicable Diseases Intelligence, 2016. Canberra: Australian Government
p.000049: Department of Health; 2016 (http://www.health.gov.au/internet/main/publishing.
p.000049: nsf/Content/cda-surveil-surv_sys.htm).
p.000049: 14. Borgdorff MW, Motarjemi Y. Surveillance of foodborne diseases: What are the options? Geneva: World Health
p.000049: Organization; 1997.
p.000049: 15. Danciu I, Cowan JD, Basford M, Wang X, Saip A, Osgood S, et al. Secondary use of clinical data: the Vanderbilt
p.000049: approach. J Biomed Informat 2014;52:28–35.
p.000049: 16. Tatem AJ, Huang Z, Narib C, Kumar U, Kandula D, Pindolia DK, et al. Integrating rapid risk mapping and mobile
p.000049: phone call record data for strategic malaria elimination planning. Malar J 2014;13:52.
p.000049: 17. Wesolowski A, Stresman G, Eagle N, Stevenson J, Owaga C, Marube E, et al. Quantifying travel behavior for
p.000049: infectious disease research: a comparison of data from surveys and mobile phones. Sci Rep 2014;4:5678.
p.000049: 18. Lajous M, Danon L, Lopez-Ridaura R, Astley CM, Miller JC, Dowell SF, et al. Mobile messaging as surveillance
p.000049: tool during pandemic (H1N1) 2009, Mexico. Emerg Infect Dis 2010;16:1488–1489.
p.000049: 19. International health regulations. Geneva: World Health Organization; 1983.
p.000049:
p.000050: 50
p.000050: References
p.000050:
p.000050: 20. Report of the Ebola interim assessment panel. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2016
...
p.002008: 2008
p.002008: 47. Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis prevention, care and control. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2010.
p.002008: 48. Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB strategy. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2017.
p.002008: 49. Guidance for managing ethical issues in infectious disease outbreaks. Geneva: World Health Orga- nization; 2016.
p.002008: 50. Scott JC. Seeing like a state: how certain schemes to improve the human condition have failed. New Haven, CT:
p.002008: Yale University Press; 1998.
p.002008: 51. Promoting the health of refugees and migrants. Executive Board resolution 140/24. Geneva: World
p.002008: Health Organization; 2017.
p.002008: 52. Willison DJ, Ondrusek N, Dawson A, Emerson C, Ferris LE, Saginur R, et al. What makes public
p.002008: health studies ethical? Dissolving the boundary between research and practice. BMC Med Ethics 2014;15:61.
p.002008: 53. Graham J, Amos B, Plumptre T. Principles for Good Governance in the 21st Century: Policy Brief
p.002008: No. 15. Ottawa: Institute on Governance, 1993. Available at: http://iog.ca/wp-content/
p.002008: uploads/2012/12/2003_August_policybrief151.pdf
p.002008: 54. United Nations Development Programme. Chapter 8: Governance Principles, Institutional Capac- ity, and Quality.
p.002008: In Towards human resilience: sustaining MDG progress in an age of economic uncertainty. New York: United
p.002008: Nations Development Programme, 2011. Available at: http://www.
p.002008: undp.org/content/undp/en/home/librarypage/poverty-reduction/inclusive_development/towards_
p.002008: human_resiliencesustainingmdgprogressinanageofeconomicun.html54.
p.002008: 55. Expert information. Tokyo: Japan Ministry of Health, Labour and Welfare (http://www.mhlw.go.jp/
p.002008: bunya/kenkou/kekkaku-kansenshou11/dl/01_kansensho.pdf).
p.002008:
p.002008:
p.000052: 52
p.000052: References
p.000052:
p.000052: 56. German RR, Lee LM, Horan JM, Milstein RL, Pertowski CA, Waller MN, et al. Updated guidelines for evaluating
p.000052: public health surveillance systems: recommendations from the Guidelines Working Group. MMWR Recomm Rep 2001;50:1-35;
p.000052: quiz CE1-7.
p.000052: 57. Brock DW, Wikler D. Ethical challenges in long-term funding for HIV/AIDS. Health Aff (Millwood)
p.000052: 2009;28:1666–1676.
p.000052: 58. Daniels N. Accountability for reasonableness: establishing a fair process for priority setting is easier than
p.000052: agreeing on principles. BMJ 2000;321:1300–1301.
p.000052: 59. O’Neill O. Trust, trustworthiness and transparency. Brussels: European Foundation Centre; 2015.
p.000052: 60. WHO framework convention on tobacco control. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2003.
p.000052: 61. United Nations framework convention on climate change. New York, NY: United Nations; 2015.
p.000052: 62. Calain P. From the field side of the binoculars: a different view on global public health surveillance. Health
p.000052: Policy Plan 2007;22:13–20.
p.000052: 63. Gostin L, Friedman EA. Ebola: a crisis in global health leadership. Lancet 2014;384:1323–1325.
p.000052: 64. Bioethics for Every Generation: The Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues
...
Searching for indicator property:
(return to top)
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public Health Surveillance
p.000005:
p.000005: WHO guidelines on ethical issues in public health surveillance ISBN 978-92-4-151265-7
p.000005:
p.000005: © World Health Organization 2017
p.000005:
p.000005: Some rights reserved. This work is available under the Creative Commons
p.000005: Attribution-NonCommercial- ShareAlike 3.0 IGO licence (CC BY-NC-SA 3.0 IGO;
p.000005: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/igo).
p.000005:
p.000005: Under the terms of this licence, you may copy, redistribute and adapt the work for non-commercial purposes, pro- vided
p.000005: the work is appropriately cited, as indicated below. In any use of this work, there should be no suggestion that WHO
p.000005: endorses any specific organization, products or services. The use of the WHO logo is not permitted. If you adapt the
p.000005: work, then you must license your work under the same or equivalent Creative Commons licence. If you create a
p.000005: translation of this work, you should add the following disclaimer along with the suggested cita- tion: “This
p.000005: translation was not created by the World Health Organization (WHO). WHO is not responsible for the content or accuracy
p.000005: of this translation. The original English edition shall be the binding and authentic edition”.
p.000005:
p.000005: Any mediation relating to disputes arising under the licence shall be conducted in accordance with the media- tion
p.000005: rules of the World Intellectual Property Organization.
p.000005:
p.000005: Suggested citation. WHO guidelines on ethical issues in public health surveillance. Geneva: World Health
p.000005: Organization; 2017. Licence: CC BY-NC-SA 3.0 IGO.
p.000005:
p.000005: Cataloguing-in-Publication (CIP) data. CIP data are available at http://apps.who.int/iris.
p.000005:
p.000005: Sales, rights and licensing. To purchase WHO publications, see http://apps.who.int/bookorders. To submit
p.000005: requests for commercial use and queries on rights and licensing, see http://www.who.int/about/licensing.
p.000005:
p.000005: Third-party materials. If you wish to reuse material from this work that is attributed to a third party, such as
p.000005: tables, figures or images, it is your responsibility to determine whether permission is needed for that reuse and to
p.000005: obtain permission from the copyright holder. The risk of claims resulting from infringement of any
p.000005: third- party-owned component in the work rests solely with the user.
p.000005:
p.000005: General disclaimers. The designations employed and the presentation of the material in this publication do not imply
p.000005: the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of WHO concerning the legal status of any country, territory, city
p.000005: or area or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. Dotted and dashed lines
p.000005: on maps represent approximate border lines for which there may not yet be full agreement.
p.000005:
...
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Health system
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Monitoring of health system performance
p.000009: Demographic variables
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Evaluation of control measures
p.000009: Health-related events (e.g. food and drug safety, vaccine reactions)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Registries Case reports Repeated
p.000009: surveys
p.000009: Data collection tools
p.000009: Bio-banks Secondary data sources
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Types of analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Population-based (universal or sentinel sites)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Social media
p.000009:
p.000009: Estimation of incidence or prevalence
p.000009: Measurement of associations
p.000009: Assessment of trends
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Uses
p.000009: Assessment of spatial patterns
p.000009: Data mining
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy change
p.000009:
p.000009: Source: A.A. Haghdoost
p.000009: Structural intervention
p.000009: Case or epidemic detection
p.000009: Testing of hypotheses
p.000009: Implementation research
p.000009: Quality assurance
p.000009:
p.000010: 10
p.000010: Introduction
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010: shared with populations and policy-makers in a timely, appropriate manner.
p.000010:
p.000010: Yet surveillance has been the subject of some- times bitter controversy. Public health sur- veillance may
p.000010: limit not only privacy but also other civil liberties. For example, surveillance may trigger mandatory
p.000010: quarantine, isolation, or seizure of property during an epidemic (2). When surveillance involves
p.000010: name-based reporting (that is, reporting by name), it can, to the extent that populations are made aware, trigger
p.000010: profound concern about intrusions on privacy, discrimination, and stigmatization. Name-based reporting can also
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
...
p.000032: below 2 °C. (67)
p.000032:
p.000032: Guidelines
p.000033: 33
p.000033:
p.000033:
p.000033: Guideline 8. Those responsible for surveillance should identify, evaluate, minimize and disclose risks for harm before
p.000033: surveillance is conducted. Monitoring for harm should be continuous, and, when any is identified, appropriate action
p.000033: should be taken to mitigate it.
p.000033:
p.000033: Even when public health surveillance is clearly justified to promote the common good, Mem- ber States and those
p.000033: responsible for conduct- ing surveillance should remain alert to the possibility that harm can be
p.000033: caused to both individuals and communities (Table 2).
p.000033:
p.000033: This does not mean that surveillance should not be conducted. Rather, those conducting surveillance have
p.000033: an obligation to identify potential harm beforehand, to monitor for harm during and after surveillance
p.000033: and to put in place processes to mitigate harm. Without continuous monitoring, mitigation is impos- sible.
p.000033: This is vital, not only because it is wrong to cause unnecessary harm, but also because harm – to both
p.000033: individuals and communi- ties, such as loss of property value or tourism dollars – may also damage public
p.000033: trust in the programme and in public health in general. (See guidelines 5, 12 and 13 and the discus-
p.000033: sion of good governance in section III.)
p.000033:
p.000033: In some instances, countries have provided compensation for the harm that might
p.000033:
p.000033: inevitably accompany surveillance. In the con- text of SARS, Chinese Taipei gave people who were quarantined the
p.000033: equivalent of US$ 147 (68). Basic welfare benefits or sick pay for those deprived of work as a result
p.000033: of surveil- lance are other possibilities. The possibility of compensation should not, however, pose a
p.000033: barrier to surveillance (69).
p.000033:
p.000033: There are many different types of harm: eco- nomic, legal, psychological, social (and reputa- tional) and
p.000033: physical. All should be considered in relation to surveillance (70-72). For example, a migrant or a person in another
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
...
Social / Religion
Searching for indicator faith:
(return to top)
p.000045: determination of whether the threat is of suf- ficient magnitude to warrant potential damage to the integrity of and
p.000045: trust in public health sur- veillance systems. Sanctions must be in place to prevent inappropriate data-sharing
p.000045: by public health agencies and inappropriate use of data by agencies outside the public health sector.
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: WHO Immunization officers visit Quang Binh Province, Viet Nam to monitor the Measles-Rubella Immunization campaign.
p.000045: Source: WHO / WPRO /Emmanuel Eraly
p.000045:
p.000046: 46
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046: A barcode is placed at the entrance of houses. After being flashed with a smartphone, the barcode provides information
p.000046: about whether the house was controlled and declared dengue free or not.
p.000046: Source: WHO/TDR /Catalina Cardenas
p.000046:
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000047: 47
p.000047:
p.000047: V. The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000047:
p.000047: Various “non-State” actors are involved in public health surveillance, including NGOs, faith-based
p.000047: organizations, professional organizations, research institutions, funding agencies, and
p.000047: supranational agencies like WHO and the European Centre for Disease Prevention and Control. Public
p.000047: surveillance functions may even be outsourced to private companies. This may be a cause of concern, as
p.000047: the data may no longer be owned by and accessible to State agencies. Nevertheless, the vicissitudes of
p.000047: surveillance mean that any set of ethical guidelines must cross boundaries – not only national boundaries
p.000047: but lines that have traditionally separated the public from the private (93).
p.000047:
p.000047: The problem of blurred boundaries has become even more complicated in the era of big data. By
p.000047: “big data”, we refer to both the increased volume of data that can now be col- lected and stored, usually in digital
p.000047: form, and the computational power available to pro- cess it rapidly. The ubiquitous use of personal
p.000047: computers, smartphones, wearable devices, closed-circuit cameras, genetic sequencers, semi-autonomous
p.000047: drones, and other technol- ogies means that we produce a steady stream of digital data.
p.000047:
p.000047: A data-centric technological revolution has generated great enthusiasm about the emerg- ing potential
p.000047: benefits of mining electronic health records, genomic data and other biolog- ical materials, social media
p.000047: communications, satellite imagery and other digital datasets to identify emerging disease threats,
p.000047: interrupt foodborne disease outbreaks and improve col- laboration among public health organizations. Drones have been
p.000047: hailed as a “game changer” in disease surveillance. Some have argued that
p.000047:
...
Social / Student
Searching for indicator student:
(return to top)
p.000043: practice but is ethically imperative. Ethically appropriate, rapid shar- ing of data can help in
p.000043: identifying etiological factors; predicting disease spread; evaluating existing and novel treatment,
p.000043: symptomatic care and preventive measures; and guiding
p.000043: the deployment of limited resources. As dis- cussed in the WHO guidance on managing ethical issues in
p.000043: infectious disease outbreaks (49), clinical and research data that are crucial for emergency response should also be
p.000043: shared. Data-sharing is also an obligation under the IHR in both health emergencies and infectious disease
p.000043: outbreaks.
p.000043: As part of continuous pre-epidemic prepared- ness, countries should review their laws, poli- cies and practices on
p.000043: data sharing to ensure that they adequately protect the confiden- tiality of personal information
p.000043: and address other relevant ethical questions, such as set- tling disputes about the ownership or control of
p.000043: surveillance data. Efforts should be made to ensure that rapid sharing of surveillance information with
p.000043: immediate implications for protecting public health and advancing the common good should not preclude
p.000043: subse- quent publication in a scientific journal (87).
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043: Medical student and district surveillance officer investigating suspected Ebola cases in Western Region of
p.000043: Sierra Leone.
p.000043: Source: WHO /Stéphane Saporito
p.000043:
p.000044: 44
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health agencies may use or share surveillance data
p.000044: for research purposes.
p.000044:
p.000044: Surveillance data have often served as a foun- dation for important public health research (88-90). For example,
p.000044: cancer registries have been used in longitudinal epidemiological studies on survival and treatment
p.000044: efficacy. It may be permissible to share surveillance data with researchers undertaking studies that (i) are
p.000044: sufficiently important for advancement of the common good and (ii) would not be feasible without access
p.000044: to the surveillance data in question. There may sometimes be disagreement about what should be con-
p.000044: sidered “sufficiently important” research to justify sharing of surveillance data for research
p.000044: purposes. This is a matter that local governments, public health authorities and/ or research ethics committees
p.000044: (as described below) should judge, taking into account the considerations and guidelines set out in this
p.000044: document.
p.000044:
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
...
Social / Threat of Stigma
Searching for indicator stigma:
(return to top)
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
p.000010: when a public health crisis becomes a “threat to international peace and security” does surveillance become a
p.000010: priority for wealthy countries (3). But even when sur- veillance is a priority, fragmented, unlinked or
p.000010: consolidated data sets remain a problem for their effective use for public health purposes.
p.000010:
p.000010: While surveillance is often conducted without public knowledge or concern when the risk for stigma,
p.000010: discrimination or perpetuation of inequity is high, surveillance inevitably involves conflicts of values and
p.000010: judgements about how to advance public health goals without harm- ing individuals or groups in society. Thus,
p.000010: the priorities and the distribution of resources for surveillance merit public debate, not only within
p.000010: societies but among global communi- ties. Despite landmark international guidelines on the ethics of research,
p.000010: including epidemio- logical studies, and specific ethical guidelines for surveillance of particular
p.000010: diseases and/ or in particular countries, there has been no international ethics framework to guide pub-
p.000010: lic health surveillance systems in general that spans infectious diseases, noncommunicable diseases (NCDs),
p.000010: disease outbreaks, environ- mental and occupational exposures, and even national borders. The Council for
p.000010: International
p.000010:
p.000010: Introduction
p.000011: 11
p.000011:
p.000011: Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS), the World Medical Association and others have identified this
p.000011: gap (4). It is crucial to have ethical guidance as a baseline for judging public health surveillance for
p.000011: all diseases and exposure across national borders.
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011: The fragmented, disease-specific nature of international guidance is not surprising, given the uneven,
p.000011: incomplete state of public health surveillance in both high- and low-resource settings and different national and
...
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
p.000034: however, mitigation strategies can ensure that risks for harm are dealt with adequately. Once harm or
p.000034: potential harm is identified, action must be taken to reduce the risk, or a plan must be in place for
p.000034: reducing, removing or compensating for any harm.
p.000034:
p.000034: As not all harm can be eliminated, the ben- efits of surveillance should be proportional to the risk for harm.
p.000034: Protective measures should include the way in which health authori- ties present information or
p.000034: action to the
...
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: The HIV oral test on a brothel bed in Belém do Pará, Brazil.
p.000035: Source: Laura Murray
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
...
Searching for indicator threat:
(return to top)
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
p.000010: when a public health crisis becomes a “threat to international peace and security” does surveillance become a
p.000010: priority for wealthy countries (3). But even when sur- veillance is a priority, fragmented, unlinked or
p.000010: consolidated data sets remain a problem for their effective use for public health purposes.
p.000010:
p.000010: While surveillance is often conducted without public knowledge or concern when the risk for stigma,
p.000010: discrimination or perpetuation of inequity is high, surveillance inevitably involves conflicts of values and
p.000010: judgements about how to advance public health goals without harm- ing individuals or groups in society. Thus,
p.000010: the priorities and the distribution of resources for surveillance merit public debate, not only within
p.000010: societies but among global communi- ties. Despite landmark international guidelines on the ethics of research,
p.000010: including epidemio- logical studies, and specific ethical guidelines for surveillance of particular
p.000010: diseases and/ or in particular countries, there has been no international ethics framework to guide pub-
p.000010: lic health surveillance systems in general that spans infectious diseases, noncommunicable diseases (NCDs),
p.000010: disease outbreaks, environ- mental and occupational exposures, and even national borders. The Council for
p.000010: International
p.000010:
p.000010: Introduction
p.000011: 11
p.000011:
...
p.000045: and non-state actors responsible for public welfare, sharing personally identi- fiable data is a fundamentally
p.000045: different mat- ter. Access to such personal information by agencies responsible for national security, law
p.000045: enforcement, or the allocation of social ben- efits should usually be allowed only after legal due process. To
p.000045: preserve trust in public health surveillance systems, there should be compel- ling justification for sharing
p.000045: identifiable data for non-public health uses.
p.000045:
p.000045: Inappropriate sharing of surveillance data is especially controversial in countries in which law enforcement
p.000045: or other agencies have been
p.000045:
p.000045: implicated in systematic violations of human rights. In these contexts, collaboration with law enforcement
p.000045: agencies may undermine trust in public health surveillance, creating a disincentive for seeking care or
p.000045: honest report- ing of data. This is a particular concern for individuals or groups in situations of particular
p.000045: vulnerability (92). Further, such unwarranted sharing will potentially inflict long-term dam- age on public
p.000045: health efforts more broadly.
p.000045:
p.000045: The governance mechanisms recommended in Guideline 2 should ensure that the exceptional conditions, if any, under which
p.000045: identifiable sur- veillance data may be shared are specified and made transparent. Such a review will require
p.000045: determination of whether the threat is of suf- ficient magnitude to warrant potential damage to the integrity of and
p.000045: trust in public health sur- veillance systems. Sanctions must be in place to prevent inappropriate data-sharing
p.000045: by public health agencies and inappropriate use of data by agencies outside the public health sector.
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: WHO Immunization officers visit Quang Binh Province, Viet Nam to monitor the Measles-Rubella Immunization campaign.
p.000045: Source: WHO / WPRO /Emmanuel Eraly
p.000045:
p.000046: 46
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046:
p.000046: A barcode is placed at the entrance of houses. After being flashed with a smartphone, the barcode provides information
p.000046: about whether the house was controlled and declared dengue free or not.
p.000046: Source: WHO/TDR /Catalina Cardenas
p.000046:
p.000046: Guidelines
p.000047: 47
p.000047:
p.000047: V. The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000047:
p.000047: Various “non-State” actors are involved in public health surveillance, including NGOs, faith-based
p.000047: organizations, professional organizations, research institutions, funding agencies, and
...
Searching for indicator stigmatization:
(return to top)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Registries Case reports Repeated
p.000009: surveys
p.000009: Data collection tools
p.000009: Bio-banks Secondary data sources
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Types of analysis
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Population-based (universal or sentinel sites)
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Social media
p.000009:
p.000009: Estimation of incidence or prevalence
p.000009: Measurement of associations
p.000009: Assessment of trends
p.000009:
p.000009:
p.000009: Uses
p.000009: Assessment of spatial patterns
p.000009: Data mining
p.000009:
p.000009: Policy change
p.000009:
p.000009: Source: A.A. Haghdoost
p.000009: Structural intervention
p.000009: Case or epidemic detection
p.000009: Testing of hypotheses
p.000009: Implementation research
p.000009: Quality assurance
p.000009:
p.000010: 10
p.000010: Introduction
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010: shared with populations and policy-makers in a timely, appropriate manner.
p.000010:
p.000010: Yet surveillance has been the subject of some- times bitter controversy. Public health sur- veillance may
p.000010: limit not only privacy but also other civil liberties. For example, surveillance may trigger mandatory
p.000010: quarantine, isolation, or seizure of property during an epidemic (2). When surveillance involves
p.000010: name-based reporting (that is, reporting by name), it can, to the extent that populations are made aware, trigger
p.000010: profound concern about intrusions on privacy, discrimination, and stigmatization. Name-based reporting can also
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
...
p.000033: individuals and communi- ties, such as loss of property value or tourism dollars – may also damage public
p.000033: trust in the programme and in public health in general. (See guidelines 5, 12 and 13 and the discus-
p.000033: sion of good governance in section III.)
p.000033:
p.000033: In some instances, countries have provided compensation for the harm that might
p.000033:
p.000033: inevitably accompany surveillance. In the con- text of SARS, Chinese Taipei gave people who were quarantined the
p.000033: equivalent of US$ 147 (68). Basic welfare benefits or sick pay for those deprived of work as a result
p.000033: of surveil- lance are other possibilities. The possibility of compensation should not, however, pose a
p.000033: barrier to surveillance (69).
p.000033:
p.000033: There are many different types of harm: eco- nomic, legal, psychological, social (and reputa- tional) and
p.000033: physical. All should be considered in relation to surveillance (70-72). For example, a migrant or a person in another
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
...
p.000036: (50). Every effort must be made to secure records to prevent unauthorized disclosure. Security is
p.000036: different from privacy and confidential- ity, yet it is an essential component of each. “Security” in
p.000036: this context consists of opera- tional and technological safeguards to protect personal data from unauthorized
p.000036: access or disclosure. Maintaining information security is not fool-proof, as electronic databases can be infiltrated.
p.000036:
p.000036: Governments and others who hold surveil- lance data must take appropriate techni- cal and
p.000036: organizational steps to protect data
p.000036: against accidental or unauthorized access, destruction, loss, use or disclosure, whether the data are
p.000036: collected and stored in paper or electronic (digital) format. All personnel with access to public
p.000036: health surveillance data should be trained annually in data security pro- cedures and made aware of their
p.000036: professional ethical responsibility to protect the data and the public. The level of security must be appro-
p.000036: priate to the risks and the nature of the data to be protected, taking into account the state of the art and
p.000036: the cost. In particular, sensitive information, which raises the risks of individu- als and communities for
p.000036: stigmatization or dis- crimination, should be subject to specific and especially rigorous security safeguards.
p.000036:
p.000036: The imperative to secure data should not be considered a license to refuse to use or share surveillance
p.000036: information effectively for legiti- mate public health purposes. (See guidelines 14–17 on sharing and the
p.000036: discussion in Guide- line 2 on meaningful ethics training.)
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Staff at the Medical Records Office sort through patient files at Karapitayam Hospital, Galle.
p.000036: Source: WHO / SEARO /Gary Hampton
p.000036:
p.000036:
p.000036: Guidelines
p.000037: 37
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037: Guideline 11. Under certain circumstances, the collection of names or identifiable data is justified.
p.000037:
p.000037: In some instances, the collection of names or identifiable data is both technically and ethically
p.000037: imperative. Effective surveillance may require the de-duplication of records (that is, avoidance of
p.000037: double-counting, which can lead to overestimates of incidence or prevalence).
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037:
p.000037: Names and addresses of people with dread diseases were regularly reported in newspapers until the 1960s.
p.000037: Source: New York Times, July 22, 1916. Public Domain.
p.000037:
...
p.000040: dissemination, the social value of the work cannot be realized. In the absence of appropriate
p.000040: dissemination, those who collect data, including surveillance data, might rightly be accused of exploiting the
p.000040: individuals and groups whose health data they collect and analyse in the name of the common good. The
p.000040: Nuffield Council on Bio- ethics argued that, for dissemination to be considered appropriate, those from
p.000040: whom data are collected should understand the implications of the results for both health care and prevention
p.000040: (35).
p.000040:
p.000040: Surveillance findings should be communicated concisely in a way that is understandable to a lay audience and
p.000040: sensitive to community concerns (see Guideline 7). Communica- tion should not seed panic but alert
p.000040: people to relevant risks in a sensible manner. Mass mailings, toll-free information hotlines, social media,
p.000040: newspapers, seminars, and public meetings are all possible means for conveying
p.000040: surveillance information to the communities from which data were collected and analysed and to the public.
p.000040: In resource-limited set- tings, street theatre, and folk art and other community-based methods can be
p.000040: adopted for the same purpose. Communication should also provide meaningful information for phy- sicians, hospital
p.000040: managers and other relevant target audiences.
p.000040:
p.000040: The communication of knowledge is a double- edged sword: on the one hand, knowledge may clearly empower; on
p.000040: the other, it may lead to injury, stigmatization or discrimination. A decision not to broadly publish data
p.000040: might be justified in exceptional circumstances, when doing so might cause significant harm. Likewise,
p.000040: if the affected population is so small (for example, cases of very rare cancers) that identification of
p.000040: individuals, however inadver- tent, might be inevitable, communication can be limited to preserve privacy (79).
p.000040:
p.000040: Decision-makers must also weigh the harm that could result if affected communities are not informed and
p.000040: thus deprived of knowl- edge and the ability to take action to reduce the risks and the capacity to
p.000040: engage in advo- cacy (see Guideline 13). Those responsible for public health have an affirmative duty to miti- gate
p.000040: the burdens that communication might impose on individuals or groups that are more susceptible to harm or
p.000040: injustice.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is continuing debate about when, if ever, those responsible for the design and conduct of
p.000040: surveillance are ethically obliged to inform the subjects of surveillance about individual results or
p.000040: diagnosis and then refer them to the appropriate service (80). For example, in the early days of the
p.000040: HIV epidemic, when treatment was not avail- able, blinded seroprevalence studies were considered
...
Searching for indicator stigmatized:
(return to top)
p.000025: moving from collecting and analysing data to action (see Guideline 6).
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
p.000026: include: collecting data elements that reveal stigmatized behaviour; adding new elements of data collection, such
p.000026: as measurements of CD4 counts as part of routine HIV/AIDS surveillance; adopting new uses for existing
p.000026: surveillance data, such as for case management or contact tracing; or using public health surveillance data for
p.000026: commercial or security purposes.
p.000026:
p.000026: In the case of research, review committees monitor adherence to ethics standards. Such an independent,
p.000026: impartial oversight mecha- nism allows for close scrutiny and can ensure that relevant protection is
p.000026: in place. These guidelines do not recommend mechanisms that mirror those that have emerged in the
p.000026: context of research ethics. However, public health surveillance is currently not subject to routine
p.000026: oversight. It is the obligation of coun- tries to decide the most appropriate processes for identifying and
p.000026: addressing the ethical issues that arise in public health surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Box 1 provides some examples of existing mechanisms. Any mechanism or process should ensure
p.000026: ethical implementation of sur- veillance without itself becoming an obstacle to achieving the larger public
p.000026: health goal. (We address the nexus of surveillance and research in Guideline 16.)
p.000026: Such mechanisms of ethical oversight should effectively identify the risks and ben- efits of
p.000026: surveillance and suggest measures to enhance the benefits, minimize the risks and ensure appropriate
...
Social / Threat of Violence
Searching for indicator violence:
(return to top)
p.000033: of surveil- lance are other possibilities. The possibility of compensation should not, however, pose a
p.000033: barrier to surveillance (69).
p.000033:
p.000033: There are many different types of harm: eco- nomic, legal, psychological, social (and reputa- tional) and
p.000033: physical. All should be considered in relation to surveillance (70-72). For example, a migrant or a person in another
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
...
Social / Victim of Abuse
Searching for indicator trauma:
(return to top)
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
p.000034: however, mitigation strategies can ensure that risks for harm are dealt with adequately. Once harm or
p.000034: potential harm is identified, action must be taken to reduce the risk, or a plan must be in place for
p.000034: reducing, removing or compensating for any harm.
p.000034:
p.000034: As not all harm can be eliminated, the ben- efits of surveillance should be proportional to the risk for harm.
p.000034: Protective measures should include the way in which health authori- ties present information or
p.000034: action to the
...
Searching for indicator abuse:
(return to top)
p.000033: disadvantaged group may be identified as being at higher risk for an infectious disease through surveillance, and this
p.000033: could lead to stigmatization of the group. Relevant information must be handled very carefully: reputations can
p.000033: quickly be dam- aged, with devastating results across a spec- trum that may include not-yet-documented
p.000033: types of harm (73). Various moral values and ethical principles should be weighed and bal- anced against
p.000033: each other and a judgement made about fair distribution of burdens and benefits in different surveillance
p.000033: initiatives or systems in a transparent way (see discussions of equity and good governance in section III).
p.000033:
p.000033: When, despite all efforts to mitigate harm, surveillance entails a predictable risk for harm (stigmatization,
p.000033: discrimination, expulsion or violence), additional precautions should be
p.000033:
p.000033: Table 2. Types of harm potentially related to disclosure of public health surveillance data
p.000033: Type of harm Result
p.000033: Physical Public attacks, spouse/partner abuse, domestic violence, delayed or
p.000033: inadequate treatment
p.000033: Legal Arrest, prosecution, death penalty, expulsion
p.000033: Social Discrimination, community discrimination, isolation, inability to access
p.000033: care or exclusion from care, rejection from the community
p.000033: Economic Loss of employment or revenue, loss of health care services, loss of insurance,
p.000033: increased insurance premiums, increased health care costs, limited career options, loss of life resources, forced
p.000033: relocation
p.000033: Psychological/emotional Distress, trauma, stigma
p.000033:
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Health brigades in Chiapas, Mexico, during the epidemic of H1N1 influenza, 2009.
p.000034: Source: WHO /Harold Ruiz
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: taken to protect the individuals or commu- nities at risk. The risk for serious harm may, in rare
p.000034: circumstances, be so great that sur- veillance might be difficult to justify morally. In most cases,
...
Social / education
Searching for indicator educational:
(return to top)
p.000034: the common good, they must be free to report without fear of reprisal. As surveillance officials have a
p.000034: responsibility to speak up, they should have protection. This idea is established in the IHR, which
p.000034: protects the confidentiality of those who report a veri- fiable outbreak or a public health event out- side
p.000034: official channels.
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000035: 35
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: Guideline 9. Surveillance of individuals or groups who are particularly susceptible to disease, harm or injustice is
p.000035: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
...
Social / gender
Searching for indicator gender:
(return to top)
p.000034: official channels.
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034:
p.000034: Guidelines
p.000035: 35
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035: Guideline 9. Surveillance of individuals or groups who are particularly susceptible to disease, harm or injustice is
p.000035: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000035:
p.000035: Individuals or groups in situations of height- ened vulnerability bear an undue proportion of health
p.000035: problems. Responsible authorities should make special efforts to ensure that these populations are
p.000035: included in surveillance in ways that will empower them. How exactly situations of vulnerability should be
p.000035: defined is a subject of dispute in the literature (74). Vulnerability may be diffuse, affecting large
p.000035: communities with limited economic develop- ment, limited access to health care facilities, educational
p.000035: deprivation, occupational risks or wider disadvantages in society. Public health surveillance and health
p.000035: information systems can provide valuable information to aid the development of health programmes and ser-
p.000035: vices to address their health problems and the underlying determinants of health, such as clean water, food
p.000035: security, or gender equality. To promote equity, surveillance should focus on the specific problems of these
p.000035: vulnerable communities.
p.000035:
p.000035: People with particular susceptibility to disease, harm or injustice are also at increased risk for further
p.000035: burdens, such as discrimination and stigma, attributable to surveillance activities or findings. For
p.000035: example, refugee groups and undocumented migrants with a higher disease burden may be seen, wrongly, as the cause of
p.000035: disease outbreaks. Similarly, workers with an occupational disease, such as silicosis, who lack access
p.000035: to adequate legal support may
p.000035:
p.000035: be dismissed from work rather than receiving treatment or compensation. Wherever pos- sible, susceptible
p.000035: groups should be identified before surveillance activities begin in order to minimize the risk for harm. In
p.000035: surveillance pro- grammes, there should be constant monitor- ing for (further) harm to those in conditions of
p.000035: particular vulnerability. When harm does occur, a mitigation strategy should be put in place (see Guideline 8).
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
p.000035:
...
Social / parents
Searching for indicator parent:
(return to top)
p.000031: capacity for surveillance should regularly update technical guidelines for best practices. The international
p.000031: community should help to ensure that both technical and ethical training is widely available.
p.000031:
p.000031: Surveillance may require support not only for technical capacity, however, but also for systematic,
p.000031: formal ethical evaluation and improvement, as demonstrated by global support for training in
p.000031: research ethics. Thus, international organizations also have an
p.000031:
p.000031: obligation to facilitate and encourage coun- tries to practise good governance by meeting their ethical and
p.000031: legal responsibilities. When countries fail to protect the fundamental rights or interests of individuals
p.000031: or populations in public health surveillance, international sup- port should be contingent on their rectifying
p.000031: such violations and wrongdoings.
p.000031:
p.000031: An obligation to support does not give the global community license to ignore the pri- orities of
p.000031: countries that require support or resources. International humanitarian orga- nizations have expressed
p.000031: deep concern that surveillance is too often driven by the secu- rity needs of high-income countries,
p.000031: creating ambiguities about who the chief beneficiaries of surveillance are (3). When a country’s deci- sions have been
p.000031: made in a participatory, trans- parent manner, the global community has an obligation to meet local surveillance
p.000031: aspirations that exceed or even conflict with the priorities set by international donors (62). For example, malnutrition
p.000031: may be a priority for surveillance in a country with limited resources, whereas international donors may view
p.000031: that concern as of lower priority than an infectious disease outbreak. Genuine partnerships may require reform of
p.000031: global health governance, shifting the priority from securitization, politics, and trade to “universal health
p.000031: values” (63).
p.000031:
p.000031: Too often, data are collected locally but ana- lysed at State or country level, with minimal feedback.
p.000031: Both the international community and country officials should encourage the analysis and use of
p.000031: surveillance data collected at the local level by the local level. Local analy- sis and use can enhance
p.000031: accountability and the capacity to improve population health. When local analysis is not possible,
p.000031: analyses performed at central or national level should be shared with the local level.
p.000031:
p.000032: 32
p.000032: Guidelines
p.000032:
p.000032:
p.000032:
p.000032: Guideline 7. The values and concerns of communities should be taken into account in planning, implementing and using
p.000032: data from surveillance.
p.000032:
p.000032: Officials, agencies, and organizations respon- sible for surveillance should try to engage the population
p.000032: beforehand about the goals, pro- cesses, and potential impacts (both positive and negative) of surveillance
p.000032: activities as a means of demonstrating respect for persons. When this is not possible or is not done, those
...
Social / philosophical differences/differences of opinion
Searching for indicator opinion:
(return to top)
p.000005: of this translation. The original English edition shall be the binding and authentic edition”.
p.000005:
p.000005: Any mediation relating to disputes arising under the licence shall be conducted in accordance with the media- tion
p.000005: rules of the World Intellectual Property Organization.
p.000005:
p.000005: Suggested citation. WHO guidelines on ethical issues in public health surveillance. Geneva: World Health
p.000005: Organization; 2017. Licence: CC BY-NC-SA 3.0 IGO.
p.000005:
p.000005: Cataloguing-in-Publication (CIP) data. CIP data are available at http://apps.who.int/iris.
p.000005:
p.000005: Sales, rights and licensing. To purchase WHO publications, see http://apps.who.int/bookorders. To submit
p.000005: requests for commercial use and queries on rights and licensing, see http://www.who.int/about/licensing.
p.000005:
p.000005: Third-party materials. If you wish to reuse material from this work that is attributed to a third party, such as
p.000005: tables, figures or images, it is your responsibility to determine whether permission is needed for that reuse and to
p.000005: obtain permission from the copyright holder. The risk of claims resulting from infringement of any
p.000005: third- party-owned component in the work rests solely with the user.
p.000005:
p.000005: General disclaimers. The designations employed and the presentation of the material in this publication do not imply
p.000005: the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of WHO concerning the legal status of any country, territory, city
p.000005: or area or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. Dotted and dashed lines
p.000005: on maps represent approximate border lines for which there may not yet be full agreement.
p.000005:
p.000005: The mention of specific companies or of certain manufacturers’ products does not imply that they are endorsed or
p.000005: recommended by WHO in preference to others of a similar nature that are not mentioned. Errors and omis- sions excepted,
p.000005: the names of proprietary products are distinguished by initial capital letters.
p.000005:
p.000005: All reasonable precautions have been taken by WHO to verify the information contained in this publication. However, the
p.000005: published material is being distributed without warranty of any kind, either expressed or implied. The responsibility
p.000005: for the interpretation and use of the material lies with the reader. In no event shall WHO be liable for damages
p.000005: arising from its use.
p.000005:
p.000005: Table of Contents
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: Foreword
p.000005: 5
p.000005: Acknowledgements
p.000007: 7
p.000007: I. Introduction
p.000010: 10
p.000010: II. Background
p.000014: 14
p.000014: Defining public health surveillance
p.000014: 14
p.000014: Surveillance: ethics, law and history
p.000016: 16
p.000016: III. Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000019: 19
p.000019: Existing guidelines
p.000019: 19
p.000019: Public health ethics
p.000020: 20
p.000020: IV. Guidelines
p.000024: 24
p.000024: Guideline 1. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, feasible, sustainable public health surveillance
...
p.000039: voluntary.
p.000039:
p.000039: Whether or not consent is sought, informa- tion about the nature and purpose of surveil- lance and about any risk
p.000039: for harm should be publicly accessible (see Guideline 13). Rel- evant protection and adequate governance
p.000039: mechanisms (Guideline 2 and the discussion on good governance in section III), appropri- ate ethics training
p.000039: (guidelines 2 and 6) and data security (Guideline 10) will enhance trust in surveillance systems
p.000039: and ensure protection.
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000040: 40
p.000040: Guidelines
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040: Guideline 13. Results of surveillance must be effectively communicated to relevant target audiences.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is compelling, widely accepted moral justification for dissemination of the results of surveillance to
p.000040: relevant target audiences, although it is not a substitute for ameliora- tive action on the part of those
p.000040: responsible for surveillance. At the local level, relevant target audiences include the community, community officials
p.000040: and opinion leaders, health care pro- viders (doctors, nurses, health care workers), policy-makers, health
p.000040: advocates and health volunteers. The relevant target audiences may also include Member States, national
p.000040: and international agencies, and NGOs.
p.000040:
p.000040: Although CIOMS guidelines are focused on research, they stress the importance of communicating
p.000040: results, both positive and negative, to “promote and enhance pub- lic discussion”. Without
p.000040: dissemination, the social value of the work cannot be realized. In the absence of appropriate
p.000040: dissemination, those who collect data, including surveillance data, might rightly be accused of exploiting the
p.000040: individuals and groups whose health data they collect and analyse in the name of the common good. The
p.000040: Nuffield Council on Bio- ethics argued that, for dissemination to be considered appropriate, those from
p.000040: whom data are collected should understand the implications of the results for both health care and prevention
p.000040: (35).
p.000040:
p.000040: Surveillance findings should be communicated concisely in a way that is understandable to a lay audience and
p.000040: sensitive to community concerns (see Guideline 7). Communica- tion should not seed panic but alert
p.000040: people to relevant risks in a sensible manner. Mass mailings, toll-free information hotlines, social media,
p.000040: newspapers, seminars, and public meetings are all possible means for conveying
...
Searching for indicator philosophy:
(return to top)
p.000019:
p.000020: 20
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020: and liberties are not also important ethical considerations; however, these more “social” or “public” values are
p.000020: reflected in related yet not wholly overlapping concepts that capture the broad importance of community and the
p.000020: affirmative duty to act. Some in the field use the language of solidarity (40), drawing on the communitarian
p.000020: tradition in public health (41); others describe the mutual obligations of reciprocity (42). The Nuffield
p.000020: Council on Bioethics sought to capture the duties and responsibilities of government in relation to public
p.000020: health by the concept of “steward- ship” (36).
p.000020:
p.000020: After a careful review, reflection and delibera- tion, the WHO Guidelines Development Group determined that the
p.000020: following ethical consid- erations are of particular importance for public health surveillance. They represent
p.000020: the back- bone of the guidelines:
p.000020:
p.000020: Common good: Surveillance is widely acknowledged to be a public good (43), and some of the benefits
p.000020: it pro- vides cannot be subdivided into indi- vidual private benefits because they are fundamentally shared (41,
p.000020: 44). Surveil- lance is justified, fundamentally, as a requirement for the good of all. With- out adequate
p.000020: oversight by public health bodies and the participation of individ- uals and communities, the shared ben- efits of
p.000020: surveillance are at risk. There is a complex literature on economics and moral philosophy that seeks to define and
p.000020: distinguish the terms “public good”, “public goods,” and “the com- mon good” (45). After careful delibera-
p.000020: tion, the committee adopted the term “the common good” to capture the notion of public goods more
p.000020: broadly conceived than in the narrow economic sense.
p.000020: Equity: Public health ethics is centrally concerned with the idea of equity. It is well established that
p.000020: social inequality has adverse effects on health (46). Not all inequality is within human control or is
p.000020: morally relevant. Morally prob- lematic inequality is commonly referred to as inequity. A just or fair society
p.000020: will attempt to provide equitable conditions for humans to flourish, with health as a central component.
p.000020: Equity some- times requires that the most vulnerable people receive what may appear to be disproportionate
p.000020: resources: that is, the unfair distribution of risks requires addi- tional resources to balance the scales.
p.000020: Public health surveillance can further the pursuit of equity by identifying the particular problems
p.000020: of disadvantaged populations, including global communi- ties, providing the evidence for focused health campaigns
p.000020: and identifying the basis of unfair differences in health.
p.000020:
p.000020: Respect for persons: Public health eth- ics is concerned with the rights, liberty, and other interests of individuals
p.000020: as well as overall population well-being. When- ever possible, individuals should be involved in decisions
...
Social / sex worker
Searching for indicator sex workers:
(return to top)
p.000010:
p.000010:
p.000010: shared with populations and policy-makers in a timely, appropriate manner.
p.000010:
p.000010: Yet surveillance has been the subject of some- times bitter controversy. Public health sur- veillance may
p.000010: limit not only privacy but also other civil liberties. For example, surveillance may trigger mandatory
p.000010: quarantine, isolation, or seizure of property during an epidemic (2). When surveillance involves
p.000010: name-based reporting (that is, reporting by name), it can, to the extent that populations are made aware, trigger
p.000010: profound concern about intrusions on privacy, discrimination, and stigmatization. Name-based reporting can also
p.000010: seriously harm people and property, as is seen when mob reactions supersede care, compassion and the effective
p.000010: rule of law. Concern is compounded in the absence of trust that the public health system will keep names
p.000010: secure or will release aggregated data and related information (referred to simply as “data” from
p.000010: this point forward, as records contain information that varies in type and scope) in a sensitive manner (2). In
p.000010: some countries, the HIV/AIDS pandemic sparked controversy about tracking by name those carrying the virus, but,
p.000010: even when con- fidentiality was assured, when details of risky behaviour and affected populations became
p.000010: public, groups like gay sex workers and inject- ing drug users experienced social harm such as discrimination
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
...
Economic / Economic/Poverty
Searching for indicator poor:
(return to top)
p.000041: Source: WHO / TDR /Simon Lim
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000041:
p.000042: 42
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guideline 14. With appropriate safeguards and justification, those responsible
p.000042: for public health surveillance have an obligation to share data with other national and international public health
p.000042: agencies.
p.000042:
p.000042: For a public health surveillance system to be effective, equitable, and promote the com- mon good, it must
p.000042: be capable of receiving and linking data from public agencies responsible for public health. For example, because
p.000042: of the stringent data security that has surrounded HIV surveillance, there have been situations in which data on
p.000042: HIV status have not been shared with those responsible for tuberculosis surveil- lance, obviating systematic
p.000042: identification of cases with co-infection. Public health work- ers cannot respond appropriately to swiftly
p.000042: changing infectious diseases in real time or take appropriate action in the case of chronic conditions without
p.000042: access to appropriate data. The same is true of occupational exposures. There have been examples in which
p.000042: agencies responsible for tracking occupational diseases have not shared data (despite the absence of a
p.000042: prohibition) with agencies responsible for
p.000042: worker protection and workplace regulation (23). A review of the literature indicated that much of the
p.000042: failure to share information is due to poor planning rather than safety concerns. Programmes have experienced
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
p.000042: re-shared by other agencies, except under the conditions specified elsewhere in this document, e.g. in
p.000042: guidelines 16–17. When the protection of different datasets is not equivalent, the more stringent
p.000042: privacy standard should be applied.
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000043: 43
p.000043:
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties involved in surveillance share data
p.000043: in a timely fashion.
p.000043: The collection and sharing of data are essen- tial activities in ordinary public health practice. During
...
Searching for indicator poverty:
(return to top)
p.002008: 48. Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB strategy. Geneva: World Health Organiza- tion; 2017.
p.002008: 49. Guidance for managing ethical issues in infectious disease outbreaks. Geneva: World Health Orga- nization; 2016.
p.002008: 50. Scott JC. Seeing like a state: how certain schemes to improve the human condition have failed. New Haven, CT:
p.002008: Yale University Press; 1998.
p.002008: 51. Promoting the health of refugees and migrants. Executive Board resolution 140/24. Geneva: World
p.002008: Health Organization; 2017.
p.002008: 52. Willison DJ, Ondrusek N, Dawson A, Emerson C, Ferris LE, Saginur R, et al. What makes public
p.002008: health studies ethical? Dissolving the boundary between research and practice. BMC Med Ethics 2014;15:61.
p.002008: 53. Graham J, Amos B, Plumptre T. Principles for Good Governance in the 21st Century: Policy Brief
p.002008: No. 15. Ottawa: Institute on Governance, 1993. Available at: http://iog.ca/wp-content/
p.002008: uploads/2012/12/2003_August_policybrief151.pdf
p.002008: 54. United Nations Development Programme. Chapter 8: Governance Principles, Institutional Capac- ity, and Quality.
p.002008: In Towards human resilience: sustaining MDG progress in an age of economic uncertainty. New York: United
p.002008: Nations Development Programme, 2011. Available at: http://www.
p.002008: undp.org/content/undp/en/home/librarypage/poverty-reduction/inclusive_development/towards_
p.002008: human_resiliencesustainingmdgprogressinanageofeconomicun.html54.
p.002008: 55. Expert information. Tokyo: Japan Ministry of Health, Labour and Welfare (http://www.mhlw.go.jp/
p.002008: bunya/kenkou/kekkaku-kansenshou11/dl/01_kansensho.pdf).
p.002008:
p.002008:
p.000052: 52
p.000052: References
p.000052:
p.000052: 56. German RR, Lee LM, Horan JM, Milstein RL, Pertowski CA, Waller MN, et al. Updated guidelines for evaluating
p.000052: public health surveillance systems: recommendations from the Guidelines Working Group. MMWR Recomm Rep 2001;50:1-35;
p.000052: quiz CE1-7.
p.000052: 57. Brock DW, Wikler D. Ethical challenges in long-term funding for HIV/AIDS. Health Aff (Millwood)
p.000052: 2009;28:1666–1676.
p.000052: 58. Daniels N. Accountability for reasonableness: establishing a fair process for priority setting is easier than
p.000052: agreeing on principles. BMJ 2000;321:1300–1301.
p.000052: 59. O’Neill O. Trust, trustworthiness and transparency. Brussels: European Foundation Centre; 2015.
p.000052: 60. WHO framework convention on tobacco control. Geneva: World Health Organization; 2003.
p.000052: 61. United Nations framework convention on climate change. New York, NY: United Nations; 2015.
p.000052: 62. Calain P. From the field side of the binoculars: a different view on global public health surveillance. Health
p.000052: Policy Plan 2007;22:13–20.
p.000052: 63. Gostin L, Friedman EA. Ebola: a crisis in global health leadership. Lancet 2014;384:1323–1325.
p.000052: 64. Bioethics for Every Generation: The Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues
p.000052: [Available from: https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/node/5678.html]
...
Searching for indicator low-income:
(return to top)
p.000010: and stigmatization. Because of these concerns, the HIV/AIDS epidemic spurred ethical and regulatory
p.000010: guidelines at both national and international levels that could be used in planning, collecting and then
p.000010: using personal and aggregated data.
p.000010:
p.000010: Just as often, however, failure to conduct public health surveillance has generated political and ethical controversy
p.000010: because of concern that “what doesn’t get counted doesn’t count”. Environmental and occupational
p.000010: health advocates, for example, have long made this argument. Even for events deemed critically
p.000010: important, yawning gaps in surveillance remain. The 2014–2016 Ebola virus disease crisis dramatically
p.000010: underscored the potentially devastating consequences of a lack of capacity to monitor the incidence and spread of
p.000010: disease. An effective public health or clinical response can be seriously hampered by the absence of such
p.000010: data. But if Ebola virus disease is a high- profile example of the costs of inadequate systems and the
p.000010: importance of support from the global community for vital surveillance, many other occupational and
p.000010: environmental exposures – like asthma, silicosis and condi- tions related to exposure to arsenic or lead
p.000010: – go uncounted in both high- and low-income countries. Some commentators have argued that, too often, only
p.000010: when a public health crisis becomes a “threat to international peace and security” does surveillance become a
p.000010: priority for wealthy countries (3). But even when sur- veillance is a priority, fragmented, unlinked or
p.000010: consolidated data sets remain a problem for their effective use for public health purposes.
p.000010:
p.000010: While surveillance is often conducted without public knowledge or concern when the risk for stigma,
p.000010: discrimination or perpetuation of inequity is high, surveillance inevitably involves conflicts of values and
p.000010: judgements about how to advance public health goals without harm- ing individuals or groups in society. Thus,
p.000010: the priorities and the distribution of resources for surveillance merit public debate, not only within
p.000010: societies but among global communi- ties. Despite landmark international guidelines on the ethics of research,
p.000010: including epidemio- logical studies, and specific ethical guidelines for surveillance of particular
p.000010: diseases and/ or in particular countries, there has been no international ethics framework to guide pub-
p.000010: lic health surveillance systems in general that spans infectious diseases, noncommunicable diseases (NCDs),
p.000010: disease outbreaks, environ- mental and occupational exposures, and even national borders. The Council for
p.000010: International
p.000010:
p.000010: Introduction
...
General/Other / Impaired Autonomy
Searching for indicator autonomy:
(return to top)
p.000043: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000043: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000046: 46
p.000046: V. The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000048: 48
p.000048: References
p.000050: 50
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000004: 4
p.000004:
p.000004: Foreword
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Public health surveillance is the bedrock of outbreak and epidemic response, but it reaches
p.000004: far beyond infectious diseases. It is sometimes called the radar of public health: it allows health
p.000004: officials to map disease, spot patterns, identify causes, and target interven- tions. Surveillance, for example,
p.000004: is central to understanding the increasing global burden of noncommunicable conditions. By helping to
p.000004: determine patterns and causes of morbidity and mortality, it can help guarantee access to safe food, clean water,
p.000004: pure air, and healthy environments.
p.000004:
p.000004: Surveillance, when conducted ethically, is the foundation for programs to promote human well-being at the
p.000004: population level. It can con- tribute to reducing inequalities: pockets of suf- fering that are unfair, unjust and
p.000004: preventable cannot be addressed if they are not first made visible. But surveillance is not without risks for
p.000004: participants and sometimes poses ethical dilemmas. Issues about privacy, autonomy, equity, and the common
p.000004: good need to be con- sidered and balanced, and knowing how to do so can be challenging in practice.
p.000004:
p.000004: I am pleased to see WHO leading in this impor- tant area by placing ethics at the heart of pub- lic health
p.000004: surveillance. The WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public Health Surveillance is
p.000004: the first international framework of its kind, it fills an important gap. The goal of the guide- line development project
p.000004: was to to help policy- makers and practitioners navigate the ethical issues presented by public health
p.000004: surveillance. This document outlines 17 ethical guidelines that can assist everyone involved in public
p.000004: health surveillance, including officials in gov- ernment agencies, health workers, NGOs and the private sector.
p.000004: I gratefully acknowledge the many experts and WHO colleagues who have made important contributions to
p.000004: this publication.
p.000004:
p.000004: WHO has rightly asserted that public health surveillance, conducted in a manner that anticipates
p.000004: ethical challenges and proactively seeks to reduce unnecessary risks, provides the architecture for social
p.000004: well-being. It is now up to the global community and countries to take up this challenge and implement the guide-
p.000004: lines in their surveillance systems.
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Dr Marie-Paule Kieny Assistant Director-General Health Systems and
p.000004: Innovation
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Foreword
p.000005: 5
p.000005:
p.000005: Acknowledgements
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
...
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000017:
p.000018: 18
p.000018: Background
p.000018:
p.000018: III. Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000018:
p.000018: Existing guidelines
p.000018:
p.000018: Limited academic literature on the practice of public health surveillance addresses the major ethical questions that
p.000018: arise in data collection; when the data are actually stored, used and shared; and data dissemination. The
p.000018: academic literature is (28), however, no substitute for guidelines that go beyond current disease-
p.000018: specific, national recommendations (29).
p.000018:
p.000018: In the decades since the Second World War, both international and national bodies have proposed ethical
p.000018: principles, guidelines and laws to govern research with human sub- jects. In response to egregious
p.000018: harm inflicted on individuals coerced into clinical research, new codes of ethics uniformly prioritized indi-
p.000018: vidual self-determination and emphasized the importance of informed consent for research, while acknowledging that
p.000018: it would hardly be straightforward in complex situations to bal- ance the protection of human research
p.000018: sub- jects against the social benefit of the research. In the practice of clinical ethics, autonomy assumed a
p.000018: place of singular importance, rep- resenting a fundamental change in a moral world view (30-33).
p.000018:
p.000018: In its “International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies” in 1991, CIOMS acknowledged that
p.000018: existing guidance focused on “patients and individual subjects” was not sufficient for studies involving
p.000018: “groups” of people. After considerable controversy, a con- sensus emerged: CIOMS stressed the impor- tance of
p.000018: the principles of research ethics first set out in the Nuremberg Code but recognized that application in the
p.000018: epidemiological context would require flexibility (34). The tradition that developed was one in
p.000018: which research
p.000018:
p.000018: ethics committees could waive a requirement for informed consent when the risk posed by epidemiological
p.000018: research was “no more than minimal” and obtaining consent would make the research “impracticable” (34).
p.000018:
p.000018: While public health surveillance may share methodological strategies with epidemiologi- cal research, it is
p.000018: not simply another form of research. In surveillance a community is the subject of concern. That surveillance
p.000018: is one of the responsibilities of public health was rec- ognized in 1991 by CIOMS, which described
...
p.000019: surveillance require any kind of formal guidelines or continuous over- sight? Drawing the line between research and
p.000019: surveillance – or between research and other forms of vital social inquiry such as quality improvement,
p.000019: implementation research, oral history or even journalism – has been chal- lenging, but definitional
p.000019: solutions have (to date) proved inadequate (38, 39). Accord- ingly, a leading group of surveillance
p.000019: experts underscored the need “to move past the formal demarcation between research and
p.000019:
p.000019: practice” (29). These guidelines seek to do so, not by laying out new definitions but by setting into
p.000019: bold relief both the centrality of public health surveillance to population well- being and the need for
p.000019: appropriate ethical guidance and review – that is, for a para- digm of accountability that responds to
p.000019: the demands of public health and that is distinct from the systems that have governed research for half a
p.000019: century.
p.000019:
p.000019: Public health ethics
p.000019:
p.000019: The discipline of public health ethics has developed rapidly during the past two decades.
p.000019: Its central focus has been on articu- lating and exploring the ethical issues that arise in the pursuit of
p.000019: population health. This has resulted in a focus on concepts such as the common good, equity,
p.000019: solidarity, reci- procity, and population well-being. This is not to say that more individual values
p.000019: such as autonomy, privacy, and individual rights
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019:
p.000019: A crowd at a community event to launch a vaccination campaign.
p.000019: Source: WHO /Garry Smyth
p.000019:
p.000020: 20
p.000020: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020:
p.000020: and liberties are not also important ethical considerations; however, these more “social” or “public” values are
p.000020: reflected in related yet not wholly overlapping concepts that capture the broad importance of community and the
p.000020: affirmative duty to act. Some in the field use the language of solidarity (40), drawing on the communitarian
p.000020: tradition in public health (41); others describe the mutual obligations of reciprocity (42). The Nuffield
p.000020: Council on Bioethics sought to capture the duties and responsibilities of government in relation to public
p.000020: health by the concept of “steward- ship” (36).
p.000020:
p.000020: After a careful review, reflection and delibera- tion, the WHO Guidelines Development Group determined that the
p.000020: following ethical consid- erations are of particular importance for public health surveillance. They represent
p.000020: the back- bone of the guidelines:
p.000020:
p.000020: Common good: Surveillance is widely acknowledged to be a public good (43), and some of the benefits
p.000020: it pro- vides cannot be subdivided into indi- vidual private benefits because they are fundamentally shared (41,
...
p.000021: even in documents explicitly grounded in public health ethics, differences in language and emphasis remain.
p.000021: This docu- ment is one of three recent WHO-sponsored initiatives to develop ethical frameworks for
p.000021: disease control. Building on the original “Guidance on ethics of tuberculosis preven- tion, care and
p.000021: control” in 2010 (47), the “Ethics guidance for the implementation of the End TB Strategy” (48) addresses
p.000021: the most critical challenges to reducing the number of deaths from tuberculosis by 95% by 2030
p.000021: and the number of new cases by 90% between 2015 and 2035. The “Guidance for managing ethical issues in
p.000021: infectious disease outbreaks” (49) in 2016, in response to the outbreak of Ebola virus disease in West Africa
p.000021: in 2014–2015, underscored the importance of providing ethics guidance beyond “a spe- cific pathogen in
p.000021: isolation” to “cross-cutting ethical issues that apply to infectious disease outbreaks generally”.
p.000021:
p.000021: The three projects obviously have important continuity. All, for example, emphasize equity, justice, and the
p.000021: common good (sometimes expressed as “stewardship” or “reciproc- ity”). All stress the importance
p.000021: of respecting the dignity of persons (sometimes emphasiz- ing autonomy or privacy). Accountability and the
p.000021: importance of good governance either explicitly or implicitly informs all three. They also have
p.000021: relevant differences that reflect the subject of each. The tuberculosis guidelines, for example, address the
p.000021: problem of drug- resistant disease and thus emphasize the harm principle. The guidelines on infectious disease
p.000021: outbreaks, framed as they were by concern for groups in conditions of tremendous vulner- ability and the ways
p.000021: in which outbreaks can become crises, further amplified by fear and distrust, places greater emphasis on
p.000021: human rights. Given the need to make decisions in
p.000021:
p.000022: 22
p.000022: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022:
p.000022: the face of uncertainty, they also stress utility, proportionality and efficacy.
p.000022:
p.000022: The ethical considerations outlined above and repeated and amplified in the guidelines that follow are, in the
p.000022: estimation of this commit- tee, central to justification of surveillance as a core activity, beyond outbreaks
p.000022: or infectious disease situations. They must be applied in situations that may vary in fundamental ways. The
p.000022: guidelines recognize that trade-offs of values are sometimes inevitable. The local tra- ditions and
p.000022: priorities in countries may some- times result in a different balance between competing values and
p.000022: priorities. It is important to stress, however, that not all trade-offs are morally acceptable. Local, national,
...
General/Other / Public Emergency
Searching for indicator emergency:
(return to top)
p.000003: Guideline 8. Those responsible for surveillance should identify, evaluate, minimize and disclose risks for harm before
p.000003: surveillance is conducted. Monitoring for harm should be continuous, and, when any is identified, appropriate action
p.000003: should be
p.000003: taken to mitigate it.
p.000034: 34
p.000034: Guideline 9. Surveillance of individuals or groups who are particularly susceptible to disease, harm or injustice is
p.000034: critical and demands careful scrutiny to avoid the
p.000034: imposition of unnecessary additional burdens.
p.000036: 36
p.000036: Guideline 10. Governments and others who hold surveillance data must ensure
p.000036: that identifiable data are appropriately secured.
p.000037: 37
p.000037: Guideline 11. Under certain circumstances, the collection of names or identifiable
p.000037: data is justified.
p.000038: 38
p.000038: Guideline 12. Individuals have an obligation to contribute to surveillance when reliable, valid, complete data sets are
p.000038: required and relevant protection is in place.
p.000038: Under these circumstances, informed consent is not ethically required. 40
p.000038: Guideline 13. Results of surveillance must be effectively communicated to
p.000038: relevant target audiences.
p.000041: 41
p.000041: Guideline 14. With appropriate safeguards and justification, those responsible for public health surveillance have an
p.000041: obligation to share data with other national and
p.000041: international public health agencies.
p.000043: 43
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties
p.000043: involved in surveillance share data in a timely fashion. 44
p.000043: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health
p.000043: agencies may use or share surveillance data for research purposes. 45
p.000043: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
p.000043: to take action against individuals or for uses unrelated to public health.
p.000046: 46
p.000046: V. The shifting boundaries of surveillance
p.000048: 48
p.000048: References
p.000050: 50
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000050:
p.000004: 4
p.000004:
p.000004: Foreword
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Public health surveillance is the bedrock of outbreak and epidemic response, but it reaches
p.000004: far beyond infectious diseases. It is sometimes called the radar of public health: it allows health
p.000004: officials to map disease, spot patterns, identify causes, and target interven- tions. Surveillance, for example,
p.000004: is central to understanding the increasing global burden of noncommunicable conditions. By helping to
p.000004: determine patterns and causes of morbidity and mortality, it can help guarantee access to safe food, clean water,
p.000004: pure air, and healthy environments.
p.000004:
p.000004: Surveillance, when conducted ethically, is the foundation for programs to promote human well-being at the
...
p.000007: Utrecht University Medical Centre, Netherlands.
p.000007:
p.000007: The support and contributions of two consul- tants is greatly appreciated: Carl H. Coleman, Seton Hall Law
p.000007: School, USA, and Michele Loi, Swiss Federal Institute of Technology, Switzerland.
p.000007:
p.000007: This guidance document benefited from the work of a literature review group, comprising: Corinna Klingler,
p.000007: Ludwig Maximilian University Munich, Germany (lead); Diego S. Silva, Simon Fraser University, Canada; Daniel
p.000007: Strech and Christopher Schürmann, Hannover Medical School, Germany; and Michael Vaughn, Colum- bia University
p.000007: School of Public Health, USA.
p.000007:
p.000007: WHO’s Global Health Ethics team extends thanks to the WHO internal steering group for its invaluable
p.000007: advice on development of the guidelines: Isabel Bergeri, Marie-Charlotte Bouesseau, Somnath Chatterji, Joan
p.000007: Helen Dzenowagis, Sergey Romualdovich Eremin, Jesus Maria Garcia Calleja, Margaret Orunya Lamunu, Anais
p.000007: Legand, Ahmed Mandil, Tim Nguyen, Bruce Jay Plotkin, Manju Rani, Leanne Margaret Riley, Pascal Ringwald, Carla
p.000007: Saenz Bresciani, Nahoko Shindo, and Matteo Zignol,
p.000007:
p.000007: as well as WHO colleagues Ronald Johnson, Vasee Moorthy, Mahnaz Vahedi, Amin Vakili, and Jihane Tawilah.
p.000007:
p.000007: The document also benefited from the work of an external review group, comprising: Larry Gostin, Georgetown Law
p.000007: Center, USA; Philip Zucs, Gaetan Guyodo, Marieke van der Werf, European Centre for Disease Prevention and
p.000007: Control, Sweden; Nijuan Xiang, Public Health Emergency Centre, Centers for Disease Control, China; Martyn Kirk,
p.000007: College of Medicine, Biol- ogy and Environment, Australian National Uni- versity, Australia; Thilaka Chinnaya, Ministry
p.000007: of Health, Malaysia; Mohammed Ben Ammar, for- merly at the Ministry of Health, Tunisia; Lorna Luco,
p.000007: Universidad del Desarollo, Institute of Bioethics, Chile; and Preet Dhillon and Shifalika Goenka, Public Health
p.000007: Foundation, India.
p.000007:
p.000007: Special thanks are extended to former interns of the Global Health Ethics team who con- tributed to this
p.000007: document: Nicholas Aagaard, Sara Birch Ares, Hannah Coakley, Christine Fisher, Antonia Fitzek, Theresa
p.000007: Fuchs, Sandrine Gehriger, Christina Heinicke, Sophie Hermann, Katalin Hetzelt, Felicitas Holzer, Patrik Hummel, Helene
p.000007: Maree Jacmon, Euzebiusz Jamrozik, Selena Knight, Pat McConville, Sarah McNeill, Jan Nieke, Julia Pemberton,
p.000007: Maansi Shahid, Alexander Shivarev, and Michael Vaughn.
p.000007:
p.000007: WHO gratefully acknowledges Phuong Bach Huynh, School of Public Health, Texas A&M University, for the design
p.000007: of the cover page.
p.000007:
p.000007: Preparation of this guidance document would not have been possible without the generous support of the Fondation
p.000007: Brocher, Switzer- land; Monash-Warwick Alliance Seed Fund Scheme project on “Ethics of Public Health
p.000007: Security”, Australia; Wellcome Trust, United Kingdom; and the Institute for Bioethics and Health Policy,
p.000007: University of Miami, USA.
p.000007:
p.000007:
p.000008: 8
p.000008: Acknowledgements
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
p.000008:
...
p.000015: plan- ning, implementing, and evaluating public health practices. Even if systems are operative, however, new,
p.000015: focused studies are required to respond to epidemiological threats. Further, public health surveillance systems not
p.000015: only rely on but may also inform and improve clinical practice.
p.000015:
p.000015: Surveillance: ethics, law and history
p.000015:
p.000015: Nation states have established surveillance sys- tems that differ in scope and purpose. Interna- tional law and
p.000015: regulation have been important means of ensuring at least a basic level of public health surveillance in
p.000015: all countries. In 1969, the WHO Member States adopted the IHR, a revision and consolidation of the
p.000015: Inter- national Sanitary Regulations, as the frame- work for strengthening health security in an
p.000015: increasingly interconnected world. They came into force in 1971 (19). The IHR impose a legal obligation on all
p.000015: Member States to have cer- tain core public health capacities, including surveillance and data collection,
p.000015: with the goal
p.000015:
p.000016: 16
p.000016: Background
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016:
p.000016: of preventing, controlling or responding to the international spread of disease.
p.000016:
p.000016: Experience with the SARS crisis of 2003 led the World Health Assembly to adopt a significant revision of the IHR
p.000016: on 23 May 2005 (9). While the IHR had originally focused on a short, fixed list of communicable diseases, the revised
p.000016: reg- ulations – IHR (2005) – allow flexibility to target any disease that may constitute a public health emergency of
p.000016: international concern. They also establish an obligation to create core capacity for surveillance and outbreak response
p.000016: to dis- ease and “public health events”. As of Novem- ber 2014, however, 48 countries had failed to communicate
p.000016: their capacity or plans, and another 81 had asked for extensions to com- ing into compliance (20). The
p.000016: recent outbreak of Ebola virus disease revealed that many countries had not satisfied their obligations
p.000016: under the IHR; only 64 countries – one third of those bound by the IHR – “had achieved these core
p.000016: capacities”. Nevertheless, while all countries are required to comply with the IHR, limited resources and
p.000016: political instability can pose obstacles to surveillance, and it may not be possible to overcome these obstacles
p.000016: with- out international assistance.
p.000016:
p.000016: The IHR (2005) are limited in the sense that they provide mainly a framework for gover- nance in
p.000016: addressing “public health emergen- cies of international concern”. The framework is neither for constructing
p.000016: comprehensive surveillance systems nor for grappling with the ethical issues posed by surveillance sys-
p.000016: tems and practices. International regulation, like national law and regulation, is an impor- tant tool
p.000016: that establishes a duty to conduct surveillance while also setting limits on that practice. What is legal,
p.000016: however, is not always ethical. Ethics is an essential tool for critically evaluating law, regulation and
...
p.000018:
p.000018: In its “International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies” in 1991, CIOMS acknowledged that
p.000018: existing guidance focused on “patients and individual subjects” was not sufficient for studies involving
p.000018: “groups” of people. After considerable controversy, a con- sensus emerged: CIOMS stressed the impor- tance of
p.000018: the principles of research ethics first set out in the Nuremberg Code but recognized that application in the
p.000018: epidemiological context would require flexibility (34). The tradition that developed was one in
p.000018: which research
p.000018:
p.000018: ethics committees could waive a requirement for informed consent when the risk posed by epidemiological
p.000018: research was “no more than minimal” and obtaining consent would make the research “impracticable” (34).
p.000018:
p.000018: While public health surveillance may share methodological strategies with epidemiologi- cal research, it is
p.000018: not simply another form of research. In surveillance a community is the subject of concern. That surveillance
p.000018: is one of the responsibilities of public health was rec- ognized in 1991 by CIOMS, which described
p.000018: surveillance in emergency outbreak situations as clearly requiring exemption from ethi- cal review and
p.000018: oversight. In dire situations, surveillance could not “await the formal approval of an ethical
p.000018: review committee” (34). Emergencies, however, accounted for only a small part of surveillance activities.
p.000018:
p.000018: Not until its 2009 revision did CIOMS guide- lines explicitly support continuous case-based public health
p.000018: surveillance (in the absence of informed consent). The revision stated, “Several considerations
p.000018: support the com- mon practice of requiring that all practitio- ners submit relevant data [to public
p.000018: health surveillance registries]: the importance of having comprehensive information … about an entire
p.000018: population, the scientific need to include all cases in order to avoid undetect- able selection bias and
p.000018: the general ethical principle that burdens and benefits should be distributed across the population.” (35)
p.000018: This position echoed that of the Nuffield Council on Bioethics in the United Kingdom. In 2007, the Council
p.000018: warned against allowing individuals to opt out of reporting, arguing, “We are aware of several examples [in
p.000018: which] consent requirements have or could have had serious negative consequences.” (36) Despite this sweeping
p.000018: endorsement of mandatory nominative case reporting without consent, the Council underscored the
p.000018: inevitability of
p.000018:
...
p.000025: advocacy directed at both the national
p.000025: and global communities, thus potentially empowering the most vulnerable. The pur- suit of equity
p.000025: establishes a warrant for sur- veillance, and the global community should provide the necessary help in
p.000025: moving from collecting and analysing data to action (see Guideline 6).
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025: Interior view: a nurse is examining two young children in the dining area of the home; the mother is standing to the
p.000025: left; further to the left is a large stove situated next to a fireplace.
p.000025: Source: The National Library of Medicine
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000025:
p.000026: 26
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guideline 2. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, effective mechanisms to ensure ethical surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Public health surveillance has inherent benefits for the functioning of the public health sys- tem, as well as
p.000026: risks. Countries should have an appropriate, effective mechanism for ensur- ing adherence to ethical standards
p.000026: in both emergency and non-emergency situations. Decisions about changing an established sur- veillance
p.000026: system can pose important ethical challenges. Examples of changes that may require ethical scrutiny
p.000026: include: collecting data elements that reveal stigmatized behaviour; adding new elements of data collection, such
p.000026: as measurements of CD4 counts as part of routine HIV/AIDS surveillance; adopting new uses for existing
p.000026: surveillance data, such as for case management or contact tracing; or using public health surveillance data for
p.000026: commercial or security purposes.
p.000026:
p.000026: In the case of research, review committees monitor adherence to ethics standards. Such an independent,
p.000026: impartial oversight mecha- nism allows for close scrutiny and can ensure that relevant protection is
p.000026: in place. These guidelines do not recommend mechanisms that mirror those that have emerged in the
p.000026: context of research ethics. However, public health surveillance is currently not subject to routine
p.000026: oversight. It is the obligation of coun- tries to decide the most appropriate processes for identifying and
p.000026: addressing the ethical issues that arise in public health surveillance.
p.000026:
p.000026: Box 1 provides some examples of existing mechanisms. Any mechanism or process should ensure
p.000026: ethical implementation of sur- veillance without itself becoming an obstacle to achieving the larger public
...
p.000042: worker protection and workplace regulation (23). A review of the literature indicated that much of the
p.000042: failure to share information is due to poor planning rather than safety concerns. Programmes have experienced
p.000042: technical dif- ficulties in sharing data, some data requiring conversion (e.g. birth year to age) in order
p.000042: to link databases (84, 85).
p.000042:
p.000042: Public health systems should establish frame- works to enable secure sharing of data (see Guideline 10)
p.000042: with other national and inter- national agencies. Early collaboration to align processes in order to avoid
p.000042: foregoing benefits or wasting resources is ethically warranted. Ethical frameworks for sharing should respect
p.000042: persons by ensuring that only the data required to fulfil a sufficiently important, legitimate public health
p.000042: purpose are shared, that data are not shared more broadly than necessary, and that data are not subsequently
p.000042: re-shared by other agencies, except under the conditions specified elsewhere in this document, e.g. in
p.000042: guidelines 16–17. When the protection of different datasets is not equivalent, the more stringent
p.000042: privacy standard should be applied.
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042:
p.000042: Guidelines
p.000043: 43
p.000043:
p.000043: Guideline 15. During a public health emergency, it is imperative that all parties involved in surveillance share data
p.000043: in a timely fashion.
p.000043: The collection and sharing of data are essen- tial activities in ordinary public health practice. During
p.000043: emergencies, data-sharing takes on increased importance because of the urgency of the situation,
p.000043: uncertainty in the face of incomplete or changing information, the com- promised response capacity of local health
p.000043: sys- tems and the heightened role of cross-border collaboration. For these reasons, “rapid data sharing is
p.000043: critical during an unfolding health emergency” (86). It not only constitutes good public health
p.000043: practice but is ethically imperative. Ethically appropriate, rapid shar- ing of data can help in
p.000043: identifying etiological factors; predicting disease spread; evaluating existing and novel treatment,
p.000043: symptomatic care and preventive measures; and guiding
p.000043: the deployment of limited resources. As dis- cussed in the WHO guidance on managing ethical issues in
p.000043: infectious disease outbreaks (49), clinical and research data that are crucial for emergency response should also be
p.000043: shared. Data-sharing is also an obligation under the IHR in both health emergencies and infectious disease
p.000043: outbreaks.
p.000043: As part of continuous pre-epidemic prepared- ness, countries should review their laws, poli- cies and practices on
p.000043: data sharing to ensure that they adequately protect the confiden- tiality of personal information
p.000043: and address other relevant ethical questions, such as set- tling disputes about the ownership or control of
p.000043: surveillance data. Efforts should be made to ensure that rapid sharing of surveillance information with
p.000043: immediate implications for protecting public health and advancing the common good should not preclude
p.000043: subse- quent publication in a scientific journal (87).
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043:
p.000043: Medical student and district surveillance officer investigating suspected Ebola cases in Western Region of
p.000043: Sierra Leone.
p.000043: Source: WHO /Stéphane Saporito
p.000043:
p.000044: 44
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guideline 16. With appropriate justification and safeguards, public health agencies may use or share surveillance data
p.000044: for research purposes.
p.000044:
p.000044: Surveillance data have often served as a foun- dation for important public health research (88-90). For example,
...
General/Other / cioms guidelines
Searching for indicator cioms:
(return to top)
p.000010: priority for wealthy countries (3). But even when sur- veillance is a priority, fragmented, unlinked or
p.000010: consolidated data sets remain a problem for their effective use for public health purposes.
p.000010:
p.000010: While surveillance is often conducted without public knowledge or concern when the risk for stigma,
p.000010: discrimination or perpetuation of inequity is high, surveillance inevitably involves conflicts of values and
p.000010: judgements about how to advance public health goals without harm- ing individuals or groups in society. Thus,
p.000010: the priorities and the distribution of resources for surveillance merit public debate, not only within
p.000010: societies but among global communi- ties. Despite landmark international guidelines on the ethics of research,
p.000010: including epidemio- logical studies, and specific ethical guidelines for surveillance of particular
p.000010: diseases and/ or in particular countries, there has been no international ethics framework to guide pub-
p.000010: lic health surveillance systems in general that spans infectious diseases, noncommunicable diseases (NCDs),
p.000010: disease outbreaks, environ- mental and occupational exposures, and even national borders. The Council for
p.000010: International
p.000010:
p.000010: Introduction
p.000011: 11
p.000011:
p.000011: Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS), the World Medical Association and others have identified this
p.000011: gap (4). It is crucial to have ethical guidance as a baseline for judging public health surveillance for
p.000011: all diseases and exposure across national borders.
p.000011:
p.000011:
p.000011: The fragmented, disease-specific nature of international guidance is not surprising, given the uneven,
p.000011: incomplete state of public health surveillance in both high- and low-resource settings and different national and
p.000011: subnational mandates for surveillance in different legal sys- tems. It is imperative to address the ethics of
p.000011: public health surveillance in a way that cuts across conventional boundaries, for a number of reasons.
p.000011:
p.000011: Public health operates in an era of global health threats, such as AIDS, severe acute
p.000011: respiratory syndrome (SARS), influenza, Ebola virus disease, Zika virus infection, obesity and coronary heart
p.000011: disease. Given the zoonotic ori- gin of many of the conditions, surveillance will increasingly involve monitoring
p.000011: the animal– human interface. For example, surveillance of food and animal feed for pathogens must be
p.000011: linked to surveillance for the same pathogens in humans.
p.000011:
p.000011: Surveillance is conducted in a context in which there have been significant advances in the capacity to collect
p.000011: and share data from previ- ously unimagined sources, such as social media or geospatial mobile phone data.
p.000011: There have been parallel technological leaps in possibili- ties for identifying disease; genetic analysis, as
...
p.000018:
p.000018: Limited academic literature on the practice of public health surveillance addresses the major ethical questions that
p.000018: arise in data collection; when the data are actually stored, used and shared; and data dissemination. The
p.000018: academic literature is (28), however, no substitute for guidelines that go beyond current disease-
p.000018: specific, national recommendations (29).
p.000018:
p.000018: In the decades since the Second World War, both international and national bodies have proposed ethical
p.000018: principles, guidelines and laws to govern research with human sub- jects. In response to egregious
p.000018: harm inflicted on individuals coerced into clinical research, new codes of ethics uniformly prioritized indi-
p.000018: vidual self-determination and emphasized the importance of informed consent for research, while acknowledging that
p.000018: it would hardly be straightforward in complex situations to bal- ance the protection of human research
p.000018: sub- jects against the social benefit of the research. In the practice of clinical ethics, autonomy assumed a
p.000018: place of singular importance, rep- resenting a fundamental change in a moral world view (30-33).
p.000018:
p.000018: In its “International guidelines for ethical review of epidemiological studies” in 1991, CIOMS acknowledged that
p.000018: existing guidance focused on “patients and individual subjects” was not sufficient for studies involving
p.000018: “groups” of people. After considerable controversy, a con- sensus emerged: CIOMS stressed the impor- tance of
p.000018: the principles of research ethics first set out in the Nuremberg Code but recognized that application in the
p.000018: epidemiological context would require flexibility (34). The tradition that developed was one in
p.000018: which research
p.000018:
p.000018: ethics committees could waive a requirement for informed consent when the risk posed by epidemiological
p.000018: research was “no more than minimal” and obtaining consent would make the research “impracticable” (34).
p.000018:
p.000018: While public health surveillance may share methodological strategies with epidemiologi- cal research, it is
p.000018: not simply another form of research. In surveillance a community is the subject of concern. That surveillance
p.000018: is one of the responsibilities of public health was rec- ognized in 1991 by CIOMS, which described
p.000018: surveillance in emergency outbreak situations as clearly requiring exemption from ethi- cal review and
p.000018: oversight. In dire situations, surveillance could not “await the formal approval of an ethical
p.000018: review committee” (34). Emergencies, however, accounted for only a small part of surveillance activities.
p.000018:
p.000018: Not until its 2009 revision did CIOMS guide- lines explicitly support continuous case-based public health
p.000018: surveillance (in the absence of informed consent). The revision stated, “Several considerations
p.000018: support the com- mon practice of requiring that all practitio- ners submit relevant data [to public
p.000018: health surveillance registries]: the importance of having comprehensive information … about an entire
p.000018: population, the scientific need to include all cases in order to avoid undetect- able selection bias and
p.000018: the general ethical principle that burdens and benefits should be distributed across the population.” (35)
p.000018: This position echoed that of the Nuffield Council on Bioethics in the United Kingdom. In 2007, the Council
p.000018: warned against allowing individuals to opt out of reporting, arguing, “We are aware of several examples [in
p.000018: which] consent requirements have or could have had serious negative consequences.” (36) Despite this sweeping
p.000018: endorsement of mandatory nominative case reporting without consent, the Council underscored the
p.000018: inevitability of
p.000018:
p.000018: Framing the ethics of surveillance
p.000019: 19
p.000019:
p.000019: making ethical judgements about the limits of surveillance (36).
p.000019: Neither CIOMS nor the Nuffield Council pro- vided more guidelines on ethics for public health surveillance,
p.000019: nor did they resolve the vexing problem of how to distinguish surveil- lance from research on human subjects.
p.000019: Are there morally relevant differences between public health surveillance and research (4, 37)? Do
p.000019: they require different general guide- lines and oversight mechanisms? Does, indeed, public health
p.000019: surveillance require any kind of formal guidelines or continuous over- sight? Drawing the line between research and
p.000019: surveillance – or between research and other forms of vital social inquiry such as quality improvement,
p.000019: implementation research, oral history or even journalism – has been chal- lenging, but definitional
p.000019: solutions have (to date) proved inadequate (38, 39). Accord- ingly, a leading group of surveillance
p.000019: experts underscored the need “to move past the formal demarcation between research and
p.000019:
p.000019: practice” (29). These guidelines seek to do so, not by laying out new definitions but by setting into
p.000019: bold relief both the centrality of public health surveillance to population well- being and the need for
p.000019: appropriate ethical guidance and review – that is, for a para- digm of accountability that responds to
p.000019: the demands of public health and that is distinct from the systems that have governed research for half a
p.000019: century.
p.000019:
p.000019: Public health ethics
p.000019:
...
p.000039: required and relevant protection is in place. Under these circumstances, informed consent is not ethically required.
p.000039:
p.000039: There is a long history of objection to public health surveillance without informed consent. Nevertheless,
p.000039: informed consent is not the default in public health surveillance. Many coun- tries have enacted laws that
p.000039: require such sys- tems to collect personal data without consent, subject to legislatively prescribed safeguards.
p.000039:
p.000039: All individuals in a population are likely to benefit from surveillance programmes. Indi- viduals,
p.000039: therefore, have a reciprocal obliga- tion to contribute to surveillance and thereby promote the common good.
p.000039: Even when the potential benefit to any one individual is small, as the epidemiologist Geoffrey Rose
p.000039: famously pointed out, the benefit to the community as a whole may be large (77). Population benefits
p.000039: provide the moral obliga- tion for individuals to contribute. If it is pos- sible to opt out (and too many
p.000039: people do so),
p.000039:
p.000039: public health might be unacceptably com- promised (78). Seeking informed consent is often not feasible in
p.000039: practice, e.g. from large populations. It may be prohibitively costly and unwarranted when the risks are
p.000039: low (as in some epidemiological research in which CIOMS has allowed waiving of consent). In some cases,
p.000039: however, consent is the norm, such as in routine descriptive health sur- veys. It is the obligation
p.000039: of the public health authorities accountable for surveillance to assess the importance and feasibility of
p.000039: seek- ing informed consent. It is important to clar- ify that, when consent is required, it must be genuinely
p.000039: voluntary.
p.000039:
p.000039: Whether or not consent is sought, informa- tion about the nature and purpose of surveil- lance and about any risk
p.000039: for harm should be publicly accessible (see Guideline 13). Rel- evant protection and adequate governance
p.000039: mechanisms (Guideline 2 and the discussion on good governance in section III), appropri- ate ethics training
p.000039: (guidelines 2 and 6) and data security (Guideline 10) will enhance trust in surveillance systems
p.000039: and ensure protection.
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000039:
p.000040: 40
p.000040: Guidelines
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040:
p.000040: Guideline 13. Results of surveillance must be effectively communicated to relevant target audiences.
p.000040:
p.000040: There is compelling, widely accepted moral justification for dissemination of the results of surveillance to
p.000040: relevant target audiences, although it is not a substitute for ameliora- tive action on the part of those
p.000040: responsible for surveillance. At the local level, relevant target audiences include the community, community officials
p.000040: and opinion leaders, health care pro- viders (doctors, nurses, health care workers), policy-makers, health
p.000040: advocates and health volunteers. The relevant target audiences may also include Member States, national
p.000040: and international agencies, and NGOs.
p.000040:
p.000040: Although CIOMS guidelines are focused on research, they stress the importance of communicating
p.000040: results, both positive and negative, to “promote and enhance pub- lic discussion”. Without
p.000040: dissemination, the social value of the work cannot be realized. In the absence of appropriate
p.000040: dissemination, those who collect data, including surveillance data, might rightly be accused of exploiting the
p.000040: individuals and groups whose health data they collect and analyse in the name of the common good. The
p.000040: Nuffield Council on Bio- ethics argued that, for dissemination to be considered appropriate, those from
p.000040: whom data are collected should understand the implications of the results for both health care and prevention
p.000040: (35).
p.000040:
p.000040: Surveillance findings should be communicated concisely in a way that is understandable to a lay audience and
p.000040: sensitive to community concerns (see Guideline 7). Communica- tion should not seed panic but alert
p.000040: people to relevant risks in a sensible manner. Mass mailings, toll-free information hotlines, social media,
p.000040: newspapers, seminars, and public meetings are all possible means for conveying
p.000040: surveillance information to the communities from which data were collected and analysed and to the public.
p.000040: In resource-limited set- tings, street theatre, and folk art and other community-based methods can be
p.000040: adopted for the same purpose. Communication should also provide meaningful information for phy- sicians, hospital
p.000040: managers and other relevant target audiences.
p.000040:
...
p.000044: to the surveillance data in question. There may sometimes be disagreement about what should be con-
p.000044: sidered “sufficiently important” research to justify sharing of surveillance data for research
p.000044: purposes. This is a matter that local governments, public health authorities and/ or research ethics committees
p.000044: (as described below) should judge, taking into account the considerations and guidelines set out in this
p.000044: document.
p.000044:
p.000044: Sharing of surveillance data for research pur- poses requires appropriate safeguards, such as ethical oversight
p.000044: (see Guideline 2), anonymiza- tion, and data security. While the kind of ethi- cal review required for conducting
p.000044: research is not appropriate for conducting public health surveillance, surveillance data should be shared only
p.000044: for research projects that have been reviewed and approved by an appropriate
p.000044: research ethics committee or another appro- priate body, consistent with international and local
p.000044: standards on the ethical conduct of research. In making decisions about granting access to surveillance data,
p.000044: ethics committees should consider the potential public health impact of research (Is the research sufficiently
p.000044: important, or does it have, in the language of CIOMS, “social value”?), the risks to the sub- jects involved, the
p.000044: measures in place to protect privacy, and the importance and feasibility of seeking consent.
p.000044:
p.000044: Striking the appropriate balance between safeguards and research advancement will sometimes be
p.000044: challenging. One controversial way of sharing sensitive information on drug use has been to delete any
p.000044: information on substance use disorders from individual clinical records released to researchers. Such protec-
p.000044: tion in the name of privacy has become the centre of controversy in the context of a wide- reaching opioid
p.000044: epidemic. One group of critics has argued that this has left researchers “fly- ing blind” (91).
p.000044:
p.000044: Researchers who have been provided with surveillance data should inform public health authorities about
p.000044: their findings. Before surveil- lance data are shared with researchers, there should be agreement about:
p.000044: appropriate data uses, restrictions on data re-sharing, adequate acknowledgement of the data source in publi- cations,
p.000044: and data destruction conditions at the end of the research phase.
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044:
p.000044: Guidelines
p.000045: 45
p.000045:
p.000045:
p.000045: Guideline 17. Personally identifiable surveillance data should not be shared with agencies that are likely to use them
...
General/Other / tri-council policy statement
Searching for indicator tri-council:
(return to top)
p.000026: and imple- menting a surveillance system.
p.000026:
p.000026: While the establishment of an indepen- dent, impartial ethics oversight mechanism is warranted,
p.000026: concrete implementation will depend on the social, political, legal, and cultural context in which surveillance
p.000026: is con- ducted (52). Research usually entails discrete projects with time-limited horizons, whereas surveillance
p.000026: usually involves continuous monitoring as opposed to a one-time review. The most appropriate mechanism for
p.000026: ethical scrutiny should be chosen in a transparent, accountable fashion. (See guidelines 2 and 5 and the
p.000026: discussion of good governance in section III.)
p.000026:
p.000026:
p.000026: Guidelines
p.000027: 27
p.000027:
p.000027:
p.000027:
p.000027: Box 1. Examples of oversight mechanisms
p.000027:
p.000027: Public Health Ontario (Canada)
p.000027:
p.000027: In 2012, Public Health Ontario published “A framework for the conduct of public health initiatives”. It
p.000027: applies an integrated approach for ethics review, in which all evidence-generating initiatives undergo ethi- cal
p.000027: scrutiny proportionate to the level of risk. Its Ethics Review Board plays a vital role in helping to ensure that
p.000027: research and other initiatives conducted by Public Health Ontario are carried out in a manner that is
p.000027: consistent with the second edition of the Federal “Tri-council policy statement on ethical conduct for
p.000027: research involving humans and other relevant regulations, policies and guidelines”. The Ethics Review Board addresses
p.000027: research, evaluation, surveillance, and quality improvement projects that involve human partici- pants, their data, or
p.000027: their biological materials. Membership of the Board complies with the provisions of the Federal policy statement with
p.000027: regard to expert representation and composition, with members selected from Public Health Ontario and public health
p.000027: units and academic institutions in Ontario. They have expertise in various public health disciplines and in
p.000027: methodology, law, and ethics; the members also include community representatives. (Source:
p.000027: https://www.publichealthontario.ca/en/About/Pages/Ethics-Review-Board.aspx)
p.000027:
p.000027: Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, Public Health Ethics Unit (USA)
p.000027:
p.000027: The Centers for Disease Control and Prevention established the Public Health Ethics Unit in the office of the Associate
p.000027: Director for Science, which collaborates with the Public Health Ethics Committee. It provides support throughout the
p.000027: institution; its aims are to “integrate the tools of ethical analysis into day-to-day operations”. It provides
p.000027: training, fosters and sustains a culture of ethical analysis, and provides guidance for and support in ethics
p.000027: consultations. (Source: https://www.cdc.gov/od/science/integrity/phethics/)
...
Orphaned Trigger Words
p.000004: good need to be con- sidered and balanced, and knowing how to do so can be challenging in practice.
p.000004:
p.000004: I am pleased to see WHO leading in this impor- tant area by placing ethics at the heart of pub- lic health
p.000004: surveillance. The WHO Guidelines on Ethical Issues in Public Health Surveillance is
p.000004: the first international framework of its kind, it fills an important gap. The goal of the guide- line development project
p.000004: was to to help policy- makers and practitioners navigate the ethical issues presented by public health
p.000004: surveillance. This document outlines 17 ethical guidelines that can assist everyone involved in public
p.000004: health surveillance, including officials in gov- ernment agencies, health workers, NGOs and the private sector.
p.000004: I gratefully acknowledge the many experts and WHO colleagues who have made important contributions to
p.000004: this publication.
p.000004:
p.000004: WHO has rightly asserted that public health surveillance, conducted in a manner that anticipates
p.000004: ethical challenges and proactively seeks to reduce unnecessary risks, provides the architecture for social
p.000004: well-being. It is now up to the global community and countries to take up this challenge and implement the guide-
p.000004: lines in their surveillance systems.
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Dr Marie-Paule Kieny Assistant Director-General Health Systems and
p.000004: Innovation
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004:
p.000004: Foreword
p.000005: 5
p.000005:
p.000005: Acknowledgements
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: This document was prepared by the WHO Global Health Ethics team, led by Andreas Reis and coordinated by
p.000005: Abha Saxena of the Depart- ment of Information, Evidence and Research in the cluster of Health Systems and Innovation.
p.000005:
p.000005: WHO extends special thanks to the co-chairs of the WHO Guidelines Development Group: Amy L. Fairchild, Texas
p.000005: A&M University School of Public Health, USA, and Co-director for the Columbia University WHO Collaborating Cen- tre
p.000005: for Bioethics, and Ali Akbar Haghdoost, Kerman University of Medical Sciences, Islamic Republic of Iran.
p.000005:
p.000005: Amy Fairchild was lead writer and chief editor. Ali Akbar Haghdoost contributed technical text and was
p.000005: responsible for ensuring the accuracy of the document with regard to the operation of surveillance systems.
p.000005: Angus Dawson and Lisa Lee contributed substantially to formulating the guiding principles and discussions. Calvin
p.000005: Ho Wai Loon provided core text on legal systems and issues. Jennifer Gibson contributed text on accountability
p.000005: and governance. Ronald Bayer, who was Chair of the Network of Collaborating Centres for most of the duration of this
p.000005: project, played a pivotal editorial role, with Ross Upshur and Carla Saenz. Ronald Bayer, Michael Selgelid, and Angus
p.000005: Dawson substantively addressed comments from the Guideline Development Group and external reviewers.
p.000005: Michael Selgelid, Andreas Reis, Amy Fairchild and Ronald Bayer prepared grant proposals to fund the work.
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005:
p.000005: WHO gratefully acknowledges the contribution of the WHO Guidelines Development Group, which shared extensive
p.000005: knowledge, original text and comments on the document. All are also co-authors of the document:
p.000005:
...
p.000023: to ethical scrutiny; (ii) the obli- gation to ensure appropriate protection and rights; and (iii)
p.000023: considerations in making deci- sions about how to communicate and share surveillance data. These guidelines
p.000023: represent a starting point for the searching, sustained discussions that public health surveillance
p.000023: demands. Like other international guidelines on research ethics, the ethics of surveillance will require
p.000023: continuous review and revision in the light of experience.
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023:
p.000023: Kim Pai factory, Bangkok, June 2015.
p.000023: Source: WHO /Diego Rodriguez
p.000023:
p.000024: 24
p.000024: Guidelines
p.000024:
p.000024:
p.000024:
p.000024: Guideline 1. Countries have an obligation to develop appropriate, feasible, sustainable public health surveillance
p.000024: systems.
p.000024: Surveillance systems should have a clear purpose and a plan for data collection, analysis, use and dissemination based
p.000024: on relevant public health priorities.
p.000024:
p.000024: Member States have an ethical duty to pro- tect population health – not only that of their citizens but that
p.000024: of all people within their borders, including refugees, undocumented workers, and individuals in
p.000024: transit (51) – and to address the disparities that characterize the distribution of morbidity and
p.000024: mortality. The duty to protect population health is the foundation of an affirmative responsibility to
p.000024: conduct public health surveillance. The exer- cise of that responsibility may be assigned to subnational
p.000024: governmental bodies.
p.000024:
p.000024: Without public health surveillance systems, population health cannot be protected and inequalities cannot
p.000024: be adequately addressed. Inattention to pressing public health needs leads to erosion of trust. Thus,
p.000024: from the per- spective of the common good, the failure of countries and the international community
p.000024: to undertake adequate public health surveil- lance represents a central moral concern. The importance of
p.000024: population health thus imposes upon States an obligation to develop systems that capture data critical to
p.000024: identifying and responding to (outbreaks of) infectious dis- eases, epidemic threats and the toll exacted
p.000024: by injuries and chronic disease, which demand environmental and occupational monitoring or investigation. A
p.000024: commitment to equity and justice can uncover the ways in which pat- terns of morbidity and mortality reflect
p.000024: and contribute to social inequality. As such com- prehensive systems are beyond the capacity of some countries,
p.000024: the international community, as described in Guideline 6, has the obligation to provide support.
p.000024: Passive systems of surveillance are often suf- ficient, such as monitoring seasonal outbreaks of influenza from
p.000024: incidence and prevalence rates that include neither names nor case veri- fication with costly laboratory tests for all
p.000024: indi- viduals with influenza-like syndromes. Even in the instance of influenza, however, systematic community-based
p.000024: surveillance provides a more accurate depiction of outbreaks. The State might have to establish active
p.000024: surveillance sys- tems, taking proactive steps, for example, to find data: this might require examining clinical
p.000024: records to ensure complete reporting and to confirm an influenza diagnosis. Cancer reg- istries in some
p.000024: countries have included such active surveillance.
p.000024:
p.000024: Surveillance systems often entail the enact- ment of regulations and statutes that impose upon clinicians,
p.000024: health care administrators or laboratories a duty to report to public health registries. To ensure
p.000024: effective surveillance of disease priorities, it is often necessary to man- date the reporting of individually
p.000024: identifiable data, including names and other socio-demo- graphic characteristics. Such intrusion on clini- cal
p.000024: confidentiality is justified when names are required to ensure the collection of accurate data, which is separate
p.000024: from the need to target interventions. But accurate data and targeted interventions both rest on the moral obligation
p.000024: to prevent harm to others and the common good or to provide the best resources to pop- ulations according to
...
p.000029: technical perspective will depend on the priority, the context and the type of sur- veillance. While some
p.000029: countries and institu- tions explicitly stress the accuracy or reliability of data (55), others value rapid
p.000029: collection of useful data over complete accuracy.
p.000029:
p.000029: Countries have obligations to ensure suf- ficient numbers of trained staff to generate and competently
p.000029: analyse surveillance data
p.000029:
p.000029: and promote quality. The quality of surveil- lance data can be improved not only by formal technical evaluation
p.000029: but also by regular audit and benchmarking against national and inter- national norms (56). Countries have an
p.000029: obli- gation to educate people who contribute to surveillance about its goals and to explain why surveillance
p.000029: is conducted, what risks might arise, how those risks can be minimized and any appropriate legal and
p.000029: ethical obligations. Individual health care workers, professional bodies, and agencies (like hospitals
p.000029: and labo- ratories), in turn, have a professional obliga- tion to support and contribute to maintaining the
p.000029: integrity of surveillance activities and to ensure that data of the best possible quality are obtained.
p.000029:
p.000029: Counterintuitively, data quality may be com- promised by widely used performance-based funding mechanisms.
p.000029: Too great an emphasis on achieving targets, linked to funding, can undermine the integrity of
p.000029: surveillance. For example, countries may be pressured to pro- duce data to secure resources, and staff
p.000029: may have to choose between providing either the data desired by funders or the correct data and risk
p.000029: losing their jobs. Realistic target-set- ting at international and national levels and broader international
p.000029: support for surveillance (Guideline 6) are possible solutions to coun- teract the scramble for funding that
p.000029: produces unreliable data.
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000029:
p.000030: 30
p.000030: Guidelines
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030:
p.000030: Guideline 5. Planning for public health surveillance should be guided by transparent governmental priority-setting.
p.000030:
p.000030: Public health surveillance involves the invest- ment of resources that could be allocated to meet other
p.000030: goals, such as clinical care or pre- vention (57). Furthermore, within the resources available for public
p.000030: health surveillance, priorities must be set. Given competing goods, the allocation of scarce resources must
p.000030: inevita- bly engage questions of equity and efficiency. As no absolute standard can guide such deter- minations, it is
p.000030: critical that decision-making be transparent, fair and open to revision (58). Governments are accountable for
p.000030: how priori- ties are set. Transparency is important because it fosters trust and creates conditions for citi-
p.000030: zens to advance the common good individually and collectively (59).
p.000030:
p.000030: Transparency is essential with respect to: (i) the aims and duration of any public health surveil- lance activity, (ii)
p.000030: the rationale for such activity relative to explicit health or health care system goals, (iii) the intended benefits
p.000030: and potential burdens to citizens and other actors of public
...
Appendix
Indicator List
Indicator | Vulnerability |
HIV | HIV/AIDS |
abuse | Victim of Abuse |
access | Access to Social Goods |
age | Age |
arrest | person under arrest |
autonomy | Impaired Autonomy |
blind | visual impairment |
blinded | visual impairment |
children | Child |
cioms | cioms guidelines |
coerced | Presence of Coercion |
criminal | criminal |
drug | Drug Usage |
educational | education |
emergencies | patients in emergency situations |
emergency | Public Emergency |
faith | Religion |
gender | gender |
hiv/aids | HIV/AIDS |
home | Property Ownership |
language | Linguistic Proficiency |
liberty | Incarcerated |
low-income | Economic/Poverty |
migrant | migrant |
nation | stateless persons |
opinion | philosophical differences/differences of opinion |
parent | parents |
party | political affiliation |
philosophy | philosophical differences/differences of opinion |
political | political affiliation |
poor | Economic/Poverty |
poverty | Economic/Poverty |
property | Property Ownership |
refugee | Refugee Status |
sex workers | sex worker |
sick | Physically Ill |
single | Marital Status |
stigma | Threat of Stigma |
stigmatization | Threat of Stigma |
stigmatized | Threat of Stigma |
student | Student |
substance | Drug Usage |
substance use | substance use |
threat | Threat of Stigma |
trauma | Victim of Abuse |
tri-council | tri-council policy statement |
violence | Threat of Violence |
volunteers | Healthy People |
vulnerability | vulnerable |
vulnerable | vulnerable |
Indicator Peers (Indicators in Same Vulnerability)
Indicator | Peers |
HIV | ['hiv/aids'] |
abuse | ['trauma'] |
blind | ['blinded'] |
blinded | ['blind'] |
drug | ['substance'] |
hiv/aids | ['HIV'] |
home | ['property'] |
low-income | ['poor', 'poverty'] |
opinion | ['philosophy'] |
party | ['political'] |
philosophy | ['opinion'] |
political | ['party'] |
poor | ['poverty', 'low-income'] |
poverty | ['poor', 'low-income'] |
property | ['home'] |
stigma | ['threat', 'stigmatization', 'stigmatized'] |
stigmatization | ['stigma', 'threat', 'stigmatized'] |
stigmatized | ['stigma', 'threat', 'stigmatization'] |
substance | ['drug'] |
threat | ['stigma', 'stigmatization', 'stigmatized'] |
trauma | ['abuse'] |
vulnerability | ['vulnerable'] |
vulnerable | ['vulnerability'] |
Trigger Words
capacity
consent
cultural
developing
ethics
harm
justice
protect
protection
risk
self-determination
sensitive
welfare
Applicable Type / Vulnerability / Indicator Overlay for this Input